Wednesday, May 30, 2007
Global Warming Is Not a Threat but the
Environmentalist Response to It Is (Full Version)
This article is the original, full version from which
three previous articles that have appeared on this blog
were excerpted. Those articles were “The
Environmentalist Noose Is Tightening” (February 9, 2007,
“Global Warming Is Not a Threat But the Environmentalist
Response to It Is” (Monday, March 05, 2007), and “Global
Warming: Environmentalism’s Threat of Hell on Earth”
(Tuesday, March 13, 2007).
Global Warming Does Not Imply a Carbon Cap
Early this winter, the UN’s Intergovernmental Panel on
Climate Change released the summary of its latest report
on global warming. It’s most trumpeted finding was that
the existence of global warming is now “unequivocal.”
Although such anecdotal evidence as January’s
snowfall in Tucson, Arizona and freezing weather in
Southern California, and February’s more than
100-inch snowfall in
upstate New York, might suggest otherwise, global
warming may indeed be a fact. It may also be a fact that
it is a by-product of industrial civilization (despite
two ice ages having apparently occurred in the face of
carbon levels in the atmosphere
16 times greater than that of today, millions of
years before mankind’s appearance on earth).
If global warming and mankind’s responsibility for it
really are facts, does anything automatically follow
from them? Does it follow that there is a need to limit
and/or reduce carbon emissions and the use of the fossil
fuels—oil, coal, and natural gas—that gives rise to the
emissions? The need for such limitation and/or rollback
is the usual assumption.
Nevertheless, the truth is that nothing whatever follows
from these facts. Before any implication for action can
be present, additional information is required.
One essential piece of information is
the comparative
valuation attached to retaining industrial civilization
versus avoiding global warming. If one
values the benefits provided by industrial civilization
above the avoidance of the losses alleged to result from
global warming, it follows that nothing should be done
to stop global warming that destroys or undermines
industrial civilization. That is, it follows that global
warming should simply be accepted as a byproduct of
economic progress and that life should go on as normal
in the face of it.
(Of course, there are projections of unlikely but
nevertheless possible extreme global warming in the face
of which conditions would be intolerable. However, as I
explain below, to deal with such a possibility, it is
necessary merely to find a different method of cooling
the earth than that of curtailing the use of fossil
fuels; I also show that such methods are already at
hand.)
In fact, if it comes, global warming, in the projected
likely range, will bring
major benefits
to much of the world. Central Canada and large portions
of Siberia will become similar in climate to New England
today. So too, perhaps, will portions of Greenland. The
disappearance of Arctic ice in summer time, will shorten
important shipping routes by thousands of miles. Growing
seasons in the North Temperate Zone will be longer.
Plant life in general will flourish because of the
presence of more carbon dioxide in the atmosphere.
Strangely, these facts are rarely mentioned. Instead,
attention is devoted almost exclusively to the negatives
associated with global warming, above all to the
prospect of rising sea levels, which the report projects
to be between 7 and 23 inches by the year 2100, a range,
incidentally, that by itself does not entail major
coastal flooding. (There are, however, projections of a
rise in sea levels of 20 feet or more over the course of
the remainder of the present millennium.)
Yes, rising sea levels may cause some islands and
coastal areas to become submerged under water and
require that large numbers of people settle in other
areas. Surely, however, the course of a century, let
alone a millennium, should provide ample opportunity for
this to occur without any necessary loss of life.
Indeed, a very useful project for the UN’s panel to
undertake in preparation for its next report would be a
plan by which the portion of the world not threatened
with rising sea levels would accept the people who are
so threatened. In other words, instead of responding to
global warming with government controls, in the form of
limitations on the emission of carbon dioxide and other
greenhouse gases, an alternative response would be
devised that would be a solution in terms of greater
freedom of migration.
In addition, the process of adaptation here in the
United States would be helped by making all areas
determined to be likely victims of coastal flooding in
the years ahead ineligible for any form of governmental
aid, insurance, or disaster relief after the expiration
of a reasonable grace period. That would spur relocation
to safer areas in advance of much of any future
flooding.
What Depends
on Industrial Civilization and Man-Made Power
As the result of industrial civilization, not only do
billions more people survive, but in the advanced
countries they do so on a level far exceeding that of
kings and emperors in all previous ages—on a level that
just a few generations ago would have been regarded as
possible only in a world of science fiction. With the
turn of a key, the push of a pedal, and the touch of a
steering wheel, they drive along highways in wondrous
machines at seventy miles an hour. With the flick of a
switch, they light a room in the middle of darkness.
With the touch of a button, they watch events taking
place ten thousand miles away. With the touch of a few
other buttons, they talk to other people across town or
across the world. They even fly through the air at six
hundred miles per hour, forty thousand feet up, watching
movies and sipping martinis in air-conditioned comfort
as they do so. In the United States, most people can
have all this, and spacious homes or apartments,
carpeted and fully furnished, with indoor plumbing,
central heating, air conditioning, refrigerators,
freezers, and gas or electric stoves, and also personal
libraries of hundreds of books, compact disks, and DVDs;
they can have all this, as well as long life and good
health—as the result of working forty hours a week.
The achievement of this marvelous state of affairs has
been made possible by the use of ever improved machinery
and equipment, which has been the focal point of
scientific and technological progress. The use of this
ever improved machinery and equipment is what has
enabled human beings to accomplish ever greater results
with the application of less and less muscular exertion.
Now inseparably connected with the use of ever improved
machinery and equipment has been the increasing use of
man-made power,
which is the distinguishing characteristic of industrial
civilization and of the Industrial Revolution, which
marked its beginning. To the relatively feeble muscles
of draft animals and the still more feeble muscles of
human beings, and to the relatively small amounts of
useable power available from nature in the form of wind
and falling water, industrial civilization has added
man-made power. It did so first in the form of steam
generated from the combustion of coal, and later in the
form of internal combustion based on petroleum, and
electric power based on the burning of any fossil fuel
or on atomic energy.
This man-made power, and the energy released by its use,
is an equally essential basis of all of the economic
improvements achieved over the last two hundred years.
It is what enables us to use the improved machines and
equipment and is indispensable to our ability to produce
the improved machines and equipment in the first place.
Its application is what enables us human beings to
accomplish with our arms and hands, in merely pushing
the buttons and pulling the levers of machines, the
amazing productive results we do accomplish. To the
feeble powers of our arms and hands is added the
enormously greater power released by energy in the form
of steam, internal combustion, electricity, or
radiation. In this way, energy use, the productivity of
labor, and the standard of living are inseparably
connected, with the two last entirely dependent on the
first.
Thus, it is not surprising, for example, that the United
States enjoys the world’s highest standard of living.
This is a direct result of the fact that the United
States has the world’s highest energy consumption per
capita. The United States, more than any other country,
is the country where intelligent human beings have
arranged for motor-driven machinery to accomplish
results for them. All further substantial increases in
the productivity of labor and standard of living, both
here in the United States and across the world, will be
equally dependent on man-made power and the growing use
of energy it makes possible. Our ability to accomplish
more and more with the same limited muscular powers of
our limbs will depend entirely on our ability to augment
them further and further with the aid of still more such
energy.*
A Free-Market
Response to Global Warming
Even if global warming is a fact, the free citizens of
an industrial civilization will have no great difficulty
in coping with it—that is, of course, if their ability
to use energy and to produce is not crippled by the
environmental movement and by government controls
otherwise inspired. The seeming difficulties of coping
with global warming, or any other large-scale change,
arise only when the problem is viewed from the
perspective of government central planners.
It would be too great a problem for government
bureaucrats to handle (as is the production even of an
adequate supply of wheat or nails, as the experience of
the whole socialist world has so eloquently shown). But
it would certainly not be too great a problem for tens
and hundreds of millions of free, thinking individuals
living under capitalism to solve. It would be solved by
means of each individual being free to decide how best
to cope with the particular aspects of global warming
that affected him.
Individuals would decide, on the basis of profit-and
loss calculations, what changes they needed to make in
their businesses and in their personal lives, in order
best to adjust to the situation. They would decide where
it was now relatively more desirable to own land, locate
farms and businesses, and live and work, and where it
was relatively less desirable, and what new comparative
advantages each location had for the production of which
goods. Factories, stores, and houses all need
replacement sooner or later. In the face of a change in
the relative desirability of different locations, the
pattern of replacement would be different. Perhaps some
replacements would have to be made sooner than
otherwise. To be sure, some land values would fall and
others would rise. Whatever happened individuals would
respond in a way that minimized their losses and
maximized their possible gains. The essential thing they
would require is the freedom to serve their
self-interests by buying land and moving their
businesses to the areas rendered relatively more
attractive, and the freedom to seek employment and buy
or rent housing in those areas.
Given this freedom, the totality of the problem would be
overcome. This is because, under capitalism, the actions
of the individuals, and the thinking and planning behind
those actions, are coordinated and harmonized by the
price system (as many former central planners of Eastern
Europe and the former Soviet Union have come to learn).
As a result, the problem would be solved in exactly the
same way that tens and hundreds of millions of free
individuals have solved greater problems than global
warming, such as redesigning the economic system to deal
with the replacement of the horse by the automobile, the
settlement of the American West, and the release of the
far greater part of the labor of the economic system
from agriculture to industry.**
Emissions
Caps Mean Impoverishment
The environmental movement does not value industrial
civilization. It fears and hates it. It does not value
human life, which it regards merely as one of earth’s
“biota,” of no greater value than any other life form,
such as spotted owls or snail darters. To it, the loss
of industrial civilization is of no great consequence.
It is a boon.
But to everyone else, it would be an immeasurable
catastrophe: the end of further economic progress and
the onset of economic retrogression, with no necessary
stopping point. Today’s already widespread economic
stagnation is the faintest harbinger of the conditions
that would follow.
A regime of emissions caps means that all technological
advances requiring an increase in the total consumption
of man-made power would be impossible to implement. At
the same time, any increase in population would mean a
reduction in the amount of man-made power available per
capita. (Greater production of atomic power, which
produces no emissions of any kind, would be an
exception. But it is opposed by the environmentalists
even more fiercely than is additional power derived from
fossil fuels.)
To gauge the consequences, simply imagine such caps
having been imposed a generation or two ago. If that had
happened, where would the power have come from to
produce and operate all of the new and additional
products we take for granted that have appeared over
these years? Products such as color television sets and
commercial jets, computers and cell phones, CDs and
DVDs, lasers and MRIs, satellites and space ships?
Indeed, the increase in population that has taken place
over this period would have sharply reduced the standard
of living, because the latter would have been forced to
rest on the foundation of the much lower per capita
man-made power of an earlier generation.
Now add to this the effects of successive
reductions
in the production of man-made power compelled by the
imposition of progressively lower ceilings on
greenhouse-gas emissions, ceilings as low as 75 or even
40 percent of today’s levels. (These ceilings have been
advocated by Britain’s Stern Report and by the United
Nations Intergovernmental Panel, respectively.) Inasmuch
as these ceilings would be
global
ceilings, any increase in greenhouse-gas emissions
taking place in countries such as China and India would
be possible only at the expense of even further
reductions in the United States, whose energy
consumption is the envy of the world.
All of the rising clamor for energy caps is an
invitation to the American people to put themselves in
chains. It is an attempt to lure them along a path
thousands of times more deadly than any military
misadventure, and one from which escape might be
impossible.
Already, led by French President Jacques Chirac, forces
are gathering to make non-compliance with emissions caps
an international crime. According to an Associated Press
report of
February 5, 2007, “Forty-Five nations joined France
in calling for a new environmental body to slow global
warming and protect the planet, a body that potentially
could have policing powers to punish violators.”
Given such developments, it is absolutely vital that the
United States never enter into any international treaty
in which it agrees to caps on greenhouse-gas emissions.
An Answer to
the Hellfire-and-Brimstone Version of Global Warming
In previous centuries it was common for Religion to
threaten those whose way of life was not to its
satisfaction, with the prospect of hellfire and
brimstone in the afterlife. Substitute for the
afterlife, life on earth in centuries to come, and it is
possible to see that environmentalism and the rest of
the left are now doing essentially the same thing. They
hate the American way of life because of its comfort and
luxury. And to frighten people into abandoning it, they
are threatening them with a global-warming version of
hellfire and brimstone.
This is not yet so open and explicit as to be obvious to
everyone. Nevertheless, it is clearly present. It is
hinted at in allusions to the possibility of temperature
increases beyond the UN report’s projected range of 3.5
to 8 degrees Fahrenheit. For example, according to
The New York
Times, “the report says there is a more
than a 1-in-10 chance of much greater warming, a risk
that many experts say is far too high to ignore.”
Environmentalist threats of hellfire and brimstone can
be expected to become more blatant and shrill if the
movement’s present efforts to frighten the people of the
United States into supporting its program appear to be
insufficient. Hellfire and brimstone is the
environmentalists’ ultimate threat.
Thus, let us assume that it were true that global
warming might proceed to such an extent as to cause
temperature and/or sea-level increases so great as to be
simply intolerable or, indeed, literally to roast and
boil the earth. Even so, it would still not follow that
industrial civilization should be abandoned or in any
way compromised. In that case, all that would be
necessary is to seek out
a different means of
deliberately cooling the earth.
It should be realized that the environmentalists’ policy
of reducing greenhouse-gas emissions is itself a policy
of cooling the earth. But it is surely among the most
stupid and self-destructive such policies as it is
possible to imagine. What it claims is that if we
destroy the energy base needed to produce and operate
the construction equipment required to build strong,
well-made, comfortable houses for hundreds of millions
of people, we shall be safer from hurricanes and floods
than if we retain and enlarge that energy base. It
claims that if we destroy our capacity to produce and
operate refrigerators and air conditioners, we shall be
better protected from hot weather than if we retain and
enlarge that capacity. It claims that if we destroy our
capacity to produce and operate tractors and harvesters,
to can and freeze food, to build and operate hospitals
and produce medicines, we shall secure our food supply
and our health better than if we retain and enlarge that
capacity. This is the meaning of the claim that
retaining this capacity will bring highly destructive
global warming, while destroying it will avoid such
global warming.***
There are
rational ways of cooling the earth if that
is what should actually be necessary, ways that would
take advantage of the vast energy base of the modern
world and of the still greater energy base that can be
present in the future if it is not aborted by the kind
of policies urged by the environmentalists.
Ironically, the core principle of one such method has
been put forward by voices within the environmental
movement itself, though not at all for this purpose.
Years ago, back in the days of the Cold War, many
environmentalists raised the specter of a
“nuclear winter.” According to them, a large-scale
atomic war could be expected to release so much
particulate matter into the atmosphere as to block out
sunlight and cause weather so severely cold that crops
would not be able to grow.
Wikipedia, the encyclopedia of the internet, describes
the mechanism as follows:
Large quantities of
aerosol particles dispersed into the atmosphere
would significantly reduce the amount of
sunlight that reached the surface, and could
potentially remain in the stratosphere for months or
even years. The ash and dust would be carried by the
midlatitude west-to-east winds, forming a uniform belt
of particles encircling the northern hemisphere from 30°
to 60°
latitude (as the main targets of most nuclear war
scenarios are located almost exclusively in these
latitudes). The dust clouds would then block out much of
the sun's light, causing surface temperatures to drop
drastically.
Certainly, there is no case to be made for an atomic
war. But there is a case for considering the possible
detonation, on uninhabited land north of 70°, say, of a
limited number of hydrogen bombs. The detonation of
these bombs would operate in the same manner as
described above, but the effect would be a belt of
particles starting at a latitude of 70° instead of 30°.
The presence of those particles would serve to reduce
the amount of sunlight reaching most of the Arctic’s
surface. The effect would be to maintain the frigid
climate of the region and to prevent the further melting
of its ice or, if necessary, to increase the amount of
its ice. Moreover, the process could be conducted
starting on a relatively small scale and proceeding
slowly. This would permit the observation of essential
empirical relationships and also allow the process to be
stopped at any time before it went too far.
This is certainly something that should be seriously
considered by anyone who is concerned with global
warming and who also desires to preserve and enhance
modern industrial civilization and retain its amenities.
If there really is any possibility of global warming so
great as to cause major disturbances, this kind of
solution should be studied and perfected. Atomic testing
should be resumed for the purpose of empirically testing
its feasibility.
If there is any remnant of the left of an earlier era,
which still respected science and technology, and
championed industrial civilization, it might be expected
to offer additional possible solutions for excessive
global warming, probably solutions of a kind requiring
grandiose construction projects. For example, one might
expect to hear from it proposals for ringing North
Africa and Australia with desalinization plants powered
by atomic energy. The purpose would be to bring massive
amounts of fresh water to the Sahara Desert and the
deserts of Australia, with the further purpose of making
possible the growth of billions of trees to absorb
carbon dioxide from the atmosphere. Another possibility
would be an alternative proposal simply to pump an
amount of sea water into confined areas in those deserts
sufficient to provide an outlet for a growing volume of
global seawater other than heavily inhabited coastal
regions. (I would not be ready to endorse any such
costly proposals, but they would be a vast improvement
over the left’s only current proposal, which is simply
the crippling of industrial civilization.)
Once people begin to put their minds to the problem, it
is possible that a variety of effective and relatively
low-cost solutions for global warming will be found. The
two essential parameters of such a solution would be the
recognition of the existence of possibly excessive
global warming, on the one side, and unswerving loyalty
to the value of the American standard of living and the
American way of life, on the other. That is, more
fundamentally, unswerving loyalty to the values of
individual freedom, continuing economic progress, and
the maintenance and further development of industrial
civilization and its foundation of man-made power.
Global warming is not a threat. But environmentalism’s
response to it is.
It claims to want to act in the name of avoiding the
risk of alleged dreadful dangers lying decades and
centuries in the future. But its means of avoiding those
alleged dangers is to rush ahead today to cripple
industrial civilization by means of crippling its
essential foundation of man-made power. In so doing, it
gives no consideration whatever to the risks of
this. Nor
does it give any consideration to any possible
alternatives to this policy. It contents itself with
offering to the public what is virtually merely the hope
and prayer of the timely discovery of radically new
alternative technologies to replace the ones it seeks to
destroy. Such pie in the sky is a nothing but a lie,
intended to prevent people from recognizing the plunge
in their standard of living that will result if the
environmentalists’ program is enacted.
If the economic progress of the last two hundred years
or more is to continue, if its existing benefits are to
be maintained, the people of the United States, and
hopefully of the rest of the world as well, must turn
their backs on environmentalism. They must recognize it
for the profoundly destructive, misanthropic philosophy
that it is.
They must solve any possible problem of global warming
on the foundation of industrial civilization, not on a
foundation of its ruins.
*The last five paragraphs, with slight adaptation, are
an excerpt from pp. 77 and 78 of my book
Capitalism: A
Treatise on Economics.
**The last four paragraphs, with slight adaptation, are
an excerpt from pp. 88 and 89 of
Capitalism.
*** The examples in this paragraph are adapted from p.
88 of Capitalism.
This article is copyright © 2007, by George Reisman.
Permission is hereby granted to reproduce and distribute
it electronically and in print, other than as part of a
book and provided that mention of the author’s web site
www.capitalism.net is included. (Email notification
is requested.) All other rights reserved. George Reisman
is the author of
Capitalism: A
Treatise on Economics (Ottawa, Illinois:
Jameson Books, 1996) and is Pepperdine University
Professor Emeritus of Economics.
Labels:
Answer to Hellfire-and-Brimstone Version of Global
Warming,
Carbon Cap,
Free-Market,
Impoverishment,
Industrial Civilization,
Man-Made Power
Sunday, May 27, 2007
Environmentalism in the Light of Menger and Mises
I
Environmentalism is the product of the collapse of
socialism in a world that is ignorant of the
contributions of von Mises—a world that does not know
what he has said that would logically explain the
collapse of socialism and, even more importantly, the
success of capitalism.
Because of ignorance of the contributions of von Mises,
the great majority of the intellectuals, and of the
general public too, which has been subjected to the
educational system fashioned and run by them, continues
to believe such things as that the profit motive is the
cause of starvation wages, exhausting hours, sweatshops,
and child labor; and of monopolies, inflation,
depressions, wars, imperialism, and racism. At the same
time, they believe that saving is hoarding and a cause
of unemployment and depressions, as is, allegedly,
economic progress in the form of improvements in
efficiency. And by the same logic, they regard war and
destruction as necessary to prevent unemployment under
capitalism. In addition, they believe that money is the
root of all evil and that competition, is “the law of
the jungle” and “the survival of the fittest.” Economic
inequality, they believe, proves that successful
businessmen and capitalists play the same social role in
capitalism as did slave owners and feudal aristocrats in
earlier times and is thus the logical and just basis for
“class warfare.”
Real, positive knowledge of the profit motive and the
price system, of saving and capital accumulation, of
money, economic competition, and economic inequality,
and of the
harmony of interests among men that results
from the joint operation of these leading features of
capitalism—all of this knowledge is almost entirely
lacking on the part of the great majority of today’s
intellectuals. To obtain such knowledge, it would be
necessary for them to read and study von Mises, who is
far and away the most important source of such
knowledge. But they have not done this.
Ignorance of the ideas of von Mises—the willful evasion
of his ideas—has enabled the last three generations of
intellectuals to go on with the delusion that capitalism
is an “anarchy of production,” a system of rampant evil,
utter madness, and continuous strife and conflict, while
socialism is a system of rational planning and order, of
morality and justice, and the ultimate universal harmony
of all mankind. For perhaps a century and a half, the
intellectuals have seen socialism as the system of
reason and science and as the ultimate goal of all
social progress. On the basis of all that they believe,
and think that they know, the great majority of
intellectuals even now cannot help but believe that
socialism should succeed and capitalism fail.
Ignorant of the contributions of von Mises, the
intellectuals were totally unprepared for the world-wide
collapse of socialism that became increasingly evident
in the last decades of the twentieth century and that
culminated in the overthrow of the communist regimes in
Eastern Europe and the former Soviet Union. Carrying
their ignorance to the depths of depravity, they have
apparently chosen to interpret the undeniable failure of
socialism not as evidence of their own ignorance
but as the failure of
reason and science. Socialism, they believe,
is the system of social organization implied by reason
and science. Its failure, they conclude, can only be the
failure of reason and science. Such is the state of
ignorance that results from ignorance of the
contributions of von Mises.
This much at least must be said here about the actual
relationship between socialism and reason. Reason is an
attribute of the individual, not the collective. As von
Mises repeatedly said, “Only the individual thinks. Only
the individual acts.” So far from being any kind of
system demanded or even remotely supported by reason,
socialism constitutes
the forcible
suppression of the reason of everyone except that of the
Supreme Dictator. He alone is to think and
plan, while all others are merely to obey and carry out
his orders. A system in which one man, or a few men,
presume to establish a monopoly on the use of reason
must, of course, fail. Its failure can certainly not be
called a failure of reason. It can no more be called a
failure of reason than it could be called a failure of
human legs if one man or a handful of men were somehow
to deprive the rest of the human race of the power to
use its legs and then, of course, found its own legs
inadequate to support the weight of the human race. So
far is the failure of socialism from being a failure of
reason that it would be much more appropriate to
describe it as a failure of
lunacy:
the lunacy of believing that the thinking and planning
of one man or a handful of men could be substituted for
the thinking and planning of tens and hundreds of
millions of men cooperating under capitalism and its
division of labor and price system. (Of course, because
they never bothered to read von Mises, the intellectuals
do not even know that ordinary people do in fact engage
in economic planning, planning that is integrated and
harmonized by the price system. From the abysmally
ignorant perspective of the intellectuals, ordinary
people are chickens without heads. Thinking and planning
are allegedly actions that only government officials can
perform.)
Because of ignorance of the contributions of von Mises,
one cannot expect very many people to know that Nazism
was actually a major form of socialism and thus that the
fifteen million or more murders for which it was
responsible should be laid at the door of socialism.
Nazism and all of its murders aside, Marxian
“scientific” socialism was responsible for more than
eighty million
murders in the twentieth century: thirty million in the
former Soviet Union, fifty million in Communist China,
and untold millions more in the satellite countries.
The great majority of the intellectual establishment
never took these latter mass murders very seriously and
certainly did not regard them as being caused by the
nature of socialism. (They did take seriously the
murders committed by the Nazis, which, in their
ignorance, they blamed on capitalism.) Even when, late
in the twentieth century, well after the great majority
of the murders had been committed and were known to the
world, President Reagan characterized the Soviet Union
as “the evil empire,” the intellectual establishment was
capable of no other response than to criticize him for
being impolite, undiplomatic, and boorish.
Now the reality is that the great majority of
intellectuals of the last several generations have blood
on their hands. Morally speaking at least, in urging the
establishment of socialism and/or in denying or ignoring
its resulting bloody consequences,
they have been
accessories to mass murder, either before
the fact or after the fact.
And, indeed, the intellectuals have some form of
awareness of their guilt. For not only do they blame
reason and science for the failure of socialism but they
now also regard reason and science, and its offshoot
technology, as
profoundly dangerous phenomena, as though
they, and not socialism and the intellectuals who made
socialism possible, had been responsible for the mass
murders. Indeed, the same intellectual quarter that a
generation or more ago urged “social engineering” has
taken the failure of social engineering so far as to now
oppose engineering of virtually any kind. The same
intellectual quarter that a generation or more ago urged
the totalitarian control of all aspects of human life
for the purpose of bringing order to what would
otherwise allegedly be chaos, now urges a policy of
laissez-faire—out
of respect for natural harmonies. Of course, it is not a
policy of laissez-faire toward human beings, who are to
be as tightly controlled as ever. Nor, of course, is it
a policy that recognizes any form of economic harmonies
among human beings. No, it is a policy of laissez-faire
toward nature in
the raw; the alleged harmonies that are to
be respected are those of so-called eco-systems.
But while the intellectuals have turned against reason,
science, and technology, they continue to support
socialism and, of course, to oppose capitalism. They now
do so in the form of environmentalism. It should be
realized that environmentalism’s goal of global limits
on carbon dioxide and other chemical emissions, as
called for in the Kyoto treaty, easily lends itself to
the establishment of world-wide central planning with
respect to a wide variety of essential means of
production. Indeed, an explicit bridge between socialism
and environmentalism is supplied by one of the most
prominent theorists of the environmental movement, Barry
Commoner, who was also the Green Party’s first candidate
for President of the United States.
The bridge is in the form of an attempted ecological
validation of one of the very first notions of Karl Marx
to be discredited—namely, Marx’s prediction of the
progressive impoverishment of the wage earners under
capitalism. Commoner attempts to salvage this notion by
arguing that what has prevented Marx’s prediction from
coming true, until now, is only that capitalism has
temporarily been able to exploit the environment. But
this process, he claims, must now come to an end, and,
as a result, the allegedly inherent conflict between the
capitalists and the workers will emerge in full force.
(For anyone interested, I quote Commoner at length in
Capitalism.)
Concerning the essential similarity between
environmentalism and socialism, I wrote:
The only difference I can see between the green movement
of the environmentalists and the old red movement of the
Communists and socialists is the superficial one of the
specific reasons for which they want to violate
individual liberty and the pursuit of happiness. The
Reds claimed that the individual could not be left free
because the result would be such things as
“exploitation,” “monopoly,” and depressions. The Greens
claim that the individual cannot be left free because
the result will be such things as destruction of the
ozone layer, acid rain, and global warming. Both claim
that centralized government control over economic
activity is essential. The Reds wanted it for the
alleged sake of achieving human prosperity. The Greens
want it for the alleged sake of avoiding environmental
damage . . . [And in the end,] [b]oth the Reds and the
Greens want someone to suffer and die; the one, the
capitalists and the rich, for the alleged sake of the
wage earners and the poor; the other, a major portion of
all mankind, for the alleged sake of the lower animals
and inanimate nature. (p. 102)
If the world’s intellectuals had been open to the
possibility that they had been wrong about the nature of
capitalism and socialism—profoundly, devastatingly
wrong—and taken the trouble to read and understand the
works of von Mises in order to learn how and why they
had been wrong, socialism would have died once and for
all with the Soviet Union, and the whole world would now
be moving toward laissez-faire capitalism and
unprecedented economic progress and prosperity. Instead,
the intellectuals have chosen to foist the doctrine of
environmentalism on the world, as a last-ditch effort to
destroy capitalism and save socialism.
II
All that I have said up to now should be understood as
in the nature of an introduction. I consider the
substance of my talk to be the refutation of the two
essential claims of the environmentalists and then a
critique of their essential policy prescription. The two
essential claims of the environmentalists, which I take
for granted are already well known to everyone, are (1)
that continued economic progress is impossible, because
of the impending exhaustion of natural resources (it is
from this notion that the slogan “reduce, reuse,
recycle” comes), and (2) that continued economic
progress, indeed, much of the economic progress that we
have had up to now, is destructive of the environment
and is therefore dangerous. The essential policy
prescription of the environmentalists is the prohibition
of self-interested individual action insofar as the
byproduct of such action when performed on a mass basis
is alleged damage to the environment. The leading
concrete example of this policy prescription is the
attempt now underway to force individuals to give up
such things as their automobiles and air conditioners on
the grounds that the byproduct of hundreds of millions
or billions of people operating such devices is to cause
global warming. And this same example, of course, is
presently the leading example of the alleged dangers of
economic progress.
The basis of my critique of the essential claims of the
environmentalists is Carl Menger’s theory of goods. The
basis of my critique of their essential policy
prescription is the spirit of individualism that runs
throughout the writings of Ludwig von Mises.
In his Principles
of Economics, Menger develops two aspects of
his theory of goods that are highly relevant to the
critique of the environmentalists’ two essential claims.
The first aspect is his recognition that what makes what
would otherwise be mere things into goods is not the
intrinsic properties of the things
but a man-made
relationship between the physical properties
of the things and the satisfaction of human needs or
wants. Menger describes four prerequisites, all of which
must be simultaneously present, in order for a thing to
become a good, or, as he often puts it, have
“goods-character.”
He writes:
If a thing is to become a good, or in other words, if it
is to acquire goods-character, all four of the following
prerequisites must be simultaneously present:
1. A human need.
2. Such properties as render the thing capable of being
brought into a causal connection with the satisfaction
of this
need.
3. Human knowledge of this causal connection.
4. Command of the thing sufficient to direct it to the
satisfaction of the need. (p. 52)
The last two of these prerequisites, it must be
stressed, are man
made. Human knowledge of the causal
connection between external material things and the
satisfaction of human needs must be discovered by man.
And command over external material things sufficient to
direct them to the satisfaction of human needs must be
established by man. For the most part, it is established
by means of a process of capital accumulation and a
rising productivity of labor.
All this has immediate bearing on the subject of natural
resources. It implies that the resources provided by
nature, such as iron, aluminum, coal, petroleum and so
on, are by no means automatically goods. Their
goods-character must be created by man, by discovering
knowledge of their respective properties that enable
them to satisfy human needs and then by establishing
command over them sufficient to direct them to the
satisfaction of human needs.
For example, iron, which has been present in the earth
since the formation of the planet and throughout the
entire presence of man on earth, did not become a good
until well after the Stone Age had ended. Petroleum,
which has been present in the ground for millions of
years, did not become a good until the middle of the
nineteenth century, when uses for it were discovered.
Aluminum, radium, and uranium also became goods only
within the last century or century and a half.
An example concerning goods-character being created only
after the establishment of command sufficient to direct
the resource provided by nature to the satisfaction of a
human need would be the case of petroleum deposits lying
deeper than existing drilling equipment could go. As
drilling equipment improved, command was established
over deposits lying at greater and greater depths. Those
deposits, to the extent that they were known, then
became goods, which they had not been before. Similarly,
for some years after the creation of the goods-character
of petroleum, those petroleum deposits containing a
significant sulfur content were unuseable for the
production of petroleum products and were therefore not
goods. Their goods-character was created only when
Rockefeller and Standard Oil developed the process of
cracking petroleum molecules, which then made sulfurous
deposits useable.
The second aspect of Menger’s theory of goods that is
highly relevant to the critique of the
environmentalists’ essential claims is his principle
that the starting point both of goods-character and of
the value of goods is
within us—within
human beings—and radiates outward from us to external
things, establishing the goods-character and value first
of things that directly satisfy our needs, such as food
and clothing, which category of goods Menger describes
as “goods of the first order,” and, second, the means of
producing goods of the first order, such as the flour to
bake bread and the cloth to make clothing, which
category of goods Menger describes as “goods of the
second order.” Goods-character and the value of goods
then proceed from goods of the second order to goods of
the third order, such as wheat, which is used to make
the flour, and cotton yarn, which is used to make the
cloth to make the clothing. From there they proceed to
goods of the fourth order, such as the equipment and
land used to produce the wheat, and the raw cotton from
which the cotton yarn is made. Thus, goods-character and
the value of goods, in Menger’s view, radiate outward
from human beings and their needs to external things
more and more remote from the direct satisfaction of
human needs.
In Menger’s own words: “The goods-character of goods of
higher order is derived from that of the corresponding
goods of lower order” (p. 63). And: “. . . the value of
goods of higher order is always and without exception
determined by the prospective value of the goods of
lower order in whose production they serve” (p. 150).
And as to the value of goods of the first order: “The
value an economizing individual attributes to a good is
equal to the importance of the particular satisfaction
that depends on his command of the good” (p. 146). “The
determining factor . . . is . . . the magnitude of
importance of those satisfactions with respect to which
we are conscious of being dependent on command of the
good” (p. 147).
In Menger’s view, it is clear that the process of
production represents a progression from goods of higher
order to goods of lower order, that is, from goods more
remote from the satisfaction of human needs and the
source of the value of all goods, to goods less remote
from the satisfaction of human needs and the source of
the value of all goods. The process of production
unmistakably appears as one of continuous enhancement of
utility, as it moves closer and closer to its ultimate
end and purpose: the satisfaction of human needs.
To apply Menger’s views to the critique of the essential
claims of environmentalism, it is first necessary to
stress the fact that in his account of things, nature’s
contribution to natural resources is implicitly much
less than is generally supposed. According to the
prevailing view, what nature has provided is the natural
resources that man exploits, that is, for example, all
of the iron mines and coal mines, all of the oil fields
and natural-gas wells, and so on. At the same time,
according to the prevailing view, man’s only connection
to these allegedly all-nature-given natural resources is
merely that he uses them up, with no means of replacing
them. It is generally thought, for example, that while
man produces such things as automobiles and
refrigerators, his sole connection to the natural
resources used in their production, such as iron ore, is
merely to use them up, with no possibility of replacing
them.
As I say, in Menger’s view, nature’s contribution to
natural resources is much less than what is usually
assumed. What nature has provided, according to Menger,
is the material stuff and the physical properties of the
deposits in these mines and wells, but it has not
provided the
goods-character of any of them. Indeed,
there was a time when none of them were goods.
The goods-character of natural resources, according to
Menger, is
created by man, when he
discovers
the properties they possess that render them capable of
satisfying human needs and when he
gains command over
them sufficient to direct them to the
satisfaction of human needs.
All that needs to be added to Menger’s view of the
man-made creation of the goods-character of natural
resources is a precise, explicit recognition of the
extent of
the things
Menger refers to that nature has provided and which are
not yet goods, but which, under the appropriate
circumstances, might become goods, or, at least, from
the domain of which things might be drawn to a greater
extent to receive goods-character by virtue of man’s
contribution to the process. In other words, what
precisely has nature provided with respect to which man
might discover causal connections to the satisfaction of
his needs and over greater portions of which he might
gain command sufficient to direct such things to the
satisfaction of his needs?
My answer to this question is that what nature has
provided is
matter and energy—matter in the form of all
the chemical elements both known and as yet unknown, and
energy, in all of its various forms. I call this
contribution of nature “the natural resources provided
by nature.” Natural resources in the much narrower sense
of “goods,” as Menger uses the term, are drawn from this
virtually infinite domain provided by nature. Natural
resources that are goods in Menger’s sense are natural
resources provided by nature that man has made useable
and accessible by virtue of discovering properties they
possess that enable them to satisfy human needs and by
virtue of gaining command over them sufficient to direct
them to the satisfaction of human needs.
What is essential here is to grasp the distinction
between the two senses of the expression “natural
resources.” First, there are natural resources as
provided by nature. Such natural resources, as I say,
are matter, in all of its elemental forms, and energy,
in all of its forms. And then, second, drawn from this
domain, are natural resources to which man has given
goods-character.
We are already familiar with the fact that an
outstanding characteristic of natural resources in the
first sense, that is, of natural resources as provided
by nature, is that none of them are intrinsically
goods—that their achievement of goods-character awaits
action by man. A further, equally important
characteristic of natural resources as provided by
nature, and which now needs to be stressed as strongly
as possible, is
the enormity of their quantity. Indeed, for
all practical purposes,
they are infinite.
Strictly speaking, they
are one and the same
with all the matter and energy in the universe.
That is the full extent of the natural resources
supplied by nature.
Thus, in one sense, the sense of useable, accessible
natural resources—that is, of goods as Menger defines
the term—the contribution of nature is
zero.
Practically nothing comes to us from nature that is
ready-made as a useable, accessible natural resource—as
a good in Menger’s sense. In another sense, however, the
natural resources that come from nature—the matter, in
the form of all the chemical elements, known and as yet
unknown, and energy in all of its forms—are virtually
infinite
in their extent. In this sense, nature’s contribution is
boundless.
Even if we limit our horizon exclusively to the planet
earth, which certainly need not be our ultimate limit,
the magnitude of natural resources supplied by nature is
mind-bogglingly huge. It is nothing less than the
entire mass of the
earth and all of the energy that goes with
it, from thunder storms in the atmosphere, a single one
of which discharges more energy than all of mankind
produces in an entire year, to the tremendous heat found
at the earth’s core in millions of cubic miles of molten
iron and nickel. Yes, the natural resources provided by
nature in the earth alone extend from the upper limits
of the earth’s atmosphere, four-thousand miles straight
down, to its center. This enormity consists of
solidly packed
chemical elements. There is not one cubic centimeter of
the earth, either on its surface or anywhere below its
surface, that is not some chemical element or other, or
some combination of chemical elements. This is nature’s
contribution to the natural resources contained in this
planet. It indicates
the incredibly
enormous extent of what is out there awaiting
transformation by man into natural resources possessing
goods-character.
And this brings me to what I consider to be the
revolutionary view of natural resources that is implied
in Menger’s theory of goods. Namely, not only does man
create the goods- character of natural resources—by
obtaining knowledge of their useful properties and then
creating their useability and accessibility by virtue of
establishing the necessary command over them—but
he also has the
ability to go on indefinitely increasing the supply of
natural resources possessing goods-character.
He enlarges
the supply of useable, accessible natural resources—that
is, natural resources possessing goods-character—as
he expands his knowledge of and physical power over
nature.
The prevailing view, that dominates the thinking of the
environmentalists and the conservationists, that there
is a scarce, precious stock of natural resources that
man’s productive activity serves merely to deplete is
wrong. Seen in its full context,
man’s productive
activity serves to enlarge the supply of useable,
accessible natural resources by converting a larger,
though still tiny, fraction of nature into natural
resources possessing goods-character. The
essential question concerning natural resources is
what fraction
of the virtual infinity that is nature does man possess
sufficient knowledge concerning and sufficient physical
command over to be able to direct it to the satisfaction
of his needs. This fraction will always be very small
indeed and will always be capable of vastly greater
further enlargement.
As I stated a moment ago, the supply of useable,
accessible natural resources expands as man expands his
knowledge of and physical power over the world and
universe. Up to now, although considerably expanded in
comparison with what it was in previous centuries, man’s
physical power over the world has been essentially
confined to the roughly thirty percent of the earth’s
surface that is not covered by sea water, and there it
has been further confined to depths that are still
measured in feet, not miles. Man is literally still just
scratching the surface of the earth, and the far lesser
part of its surface at that. And nowhere is he dealing
with nature nearly as effectively or efficiently as he
someday might.
In addition to the examples previously given with
respect to iron, petroleum, aluminum, radium, and
uranium, consider the implications for the supply of
useable, accessible natural resources of man becoming
able to mine at greater depths with less effort, to move
greater masses of earth with less effort, to break down
compounds previously beyond his power, or to do so with
less effort, to gain access to regions of the earth
previously inaccessible or to improve his access to
regions already accessible. All of these increase the
supply of useable, accessible natural resources. They do
so, of course, by virtue of creating what Menger
describes as command over things sufficient to direct
them to the satisfaction of human needs. All of them
bestow the character of goods on what had before been
mere things.
As I wrote in
Capitalism:
Today, as the result of such advances, the supply of
economically useable natural resources is enormously
greater than it was at the beginning of the Industrial
Revolution, or even just one or two generations ago.
Today, man can more easily mine at a depth of a thousand
feet than he could in the past at a depth of ten feet,
thanks to such advances as mechanical-powered drilling
equipment, high explosives, steel structural supports
for mine shafts, and modern pumps and engines. Today, a
single worker operating a bulldozer or steam shovel can
move far more earth than hundreds of workers in the past
using hand shovels. Advances in reduction methods have
made it possible to obtain pure ores from compounds
previously either altogether impossible to work with or
at least too costly to work with. Improvements in
shipping, railroad building, and highway construction
have made possible low-cost access to high-grade mineral
eposits in regions previously inaccessible or too costly
to exploit.
And, I added:
There is no limit to the further advances that are
possible. Reductions in the cost of extracting petroleum
from shale and tar sands have the potential for
expanding the supply of economically useable petroleum
by a vast multiple of what it is today. Hydrogen, the
most abundant element in the universe, may turn out to
be an economical source of fuel in the future. Atomic
and hydrogen explosives, lasers, satellite detection
systems, and, indeed, even space travel itself, open up
limitless new possibilities for increasing the supply of
economically useable mineral supplies. Advances in
mining technology that would make it possible to mine
economically at a depth of, say, ten thousand feet,
instead of the present much more limited depths, or to
mine beneath the oceans, would so increase the portion
of the earth’s mass accessible to man that all previous
supplies of accessible minerals would appear
insignificant in comparison. (p. 64)
The key point here is that, following Menger’s insights
into the nature of goods, the supply of economically
useable, accessible natural resources is
expandable.
It is enlarged as part of the same process by which man
increases the production and supply of all other goods,
namely, scientific and technological progress and saving
and capital accumulation.
The fundamental situation is this. Nature presents the
earth as an immense solidly packed ball of chemical
elements. It has also provided comparably incredible
amounts of energy in connection with this mass of
chemical elements. If, over and against this massive
contribution from nature stands motivated human
intelligence—the kind of motivated human intelligence
that a free, capitalist society so greatly encourages,
with its prospect of earning a substantial personal
fortune as the result of almost every significant
advance, there can be little doubt as to the outcome:
Man will succeed
in progressively enlarging the fraction of nature’s
contribution that constitutes goods; that
is, he will succeed in progressively enlarging the
supply of useable, accessible natural resources.
The likelihood of his success is greatly reinforced by
two closely related facts: the progressive nature of
human knowledge and the progressive nature of capital
accumulation in a capitalist society, which, of course,
is also a
rational as well as a free society. In such
a society, the stock of scientific and technological
knowledge grows from generation to generation, as each
new generation begins with all of the accumulated
knowledge acquired by previous generations and then
makes its own, fresh contribution to knowledge. This
fresh contribution enlarges the stock of knowledge
transmitted to the next generation, which in turn then
makes its own fresh contribution to knowledge, and so
on, with no fixed limit to the accumulation of knowledge
short of the attainment of omniscience.
Similarly, in such a society the stock of capital goods
grows from generation to generation. The larger stock of
capital goods accumulated in any generation on the
foundation of a sufficiently low degree of time
preference and thus correspondingly high degree of
saving and provision for the future, together with a
continuing high productivity of capital goods based on
the foundation of advancing scientific and technological
knowledge, serves to produce not only a larger and
better supply of consumers’ goods but also a comparably
enlarged and better supply of capital goods. That larger
and better supply of capital goods, continuing on the
same foundation of low time preference and advancing
scientific and technological knowledge, then serves to
further enlarge and improve the supply not only of
consumers’ goods but also of capital goods. The result
is continuing capital accumulation, on the basis of
which, from generation to generation, man is able to
confront nature in possession of growing powers of
physical command over it.
On the basis of both progressively growing knowledge of
nature and progressively growing physical power over
nature, man progressively enlarges the fraction of
nature that constitutes goods, i.e., the supply of
useable, accessible natural resources.
III
I turn now to the second aspect of Menger’s theory of
goods that relates to the critique of the essential
tenets of environmentalism, namely, his view of the
process of production as one of continuous enhancement
of utility as it moves from goods of higher order to
goods of lower order.
All that it is necessary to add to Menger’s view is
recognition once again of the fact that the earth is an
immense ball of solidly packed chemical elements. Now
these chemical elements constitute man’s external
material surroundings, i.e., his
environment.
They are the external material conditions of human life.
When these facts are kept in mind, it becomes clear that
the process of production, and the whole of economic
activity, so far from constituting a danger to man’s
environment, as the environmentalists claim, have the
inherent tendency to
improve
his environment, indeed, that that is their essential
purpose.
This becomes obvious as soon as one realizes that not
only does the entire world physically consist of nothing
but chemical elements, but also that these elements are
never destroyed. They simply reappear in different
combinations, in different proportions, in different
places. As I wrote in
Capitalism:
Apart from what has been lost in a few rockets, the
quantity of every chemical element in the world today is
the same as it was before the Industrial Revolution. The
only difference is that, because of the Industrial
Revolution, instead of lying dormant, out of man’s
control, the chemical elements have been moved about, as
never before, in such a way as to improve human life and
well-being. For instance, some part of the world’s iron
and copper has been moved from the interior of the
earth, where it was useless, to now constitute
buildings, bridges, automobiles, and a million and one
other things of benefit to human life. Some part of the
world’s carbon, oxygen, and hydrogen has been separated
from certain compounds and recombined in others, in the
process releasing energy to heat and light homes, power
industrial machinery, automobiles, airplanes, ships, and
railroad trains, and in countless other ways serve human
life. It follows that insofar as man’s environment
consists of the chemical elements iron, copper, carbon,
oxygen, and hydrogen, and his productive activity makes
them useful to himself in these ways, his environment is
correspondingly improved.
Consider further examples. To live, man needs to be able
to move his person and his goods from place to place. If
an untamed forest stands in his way, such movement is
difficult or impossible. It represents an improvement in
his environment, therefore, when man moves the chemical
elements that constitute some of the trees of the forest
somewhere else and lays down the chemical elements
brought from somewhere else to constitute a road. It is
an improvement in his environment when man builds
bridges, digs canals, opens mines, clears land,
constructs factories and houses, or does anything else
that represents an improvement in the external, material
conditions of his life. All of these things represent an
improvement in man’s material surroundings—his
environment. All of them represent the rearrangement of
nature’s elements in a way that makes them stand in a
more useful relationship to human life and well-being.
Thus, all of economic activity has as its sole purpose
the improvement of the environment—it aims exclusively
at the improvement of the external, material conditions
of human life. Production and economic activity are
precisely the means by which man adapts his environment
to himself and thereby improves it. (p. 90)
If anyone should ask how the environmentalists could
miss the fact that precisely production and economic
activity constitute the means whereby man improves his
environment, the answer is that the environmentalists do
not share Menger’s (or Western Civilization’s) starting
point of value, namely, the value of human life and
well-being. In their view, the starting point of value
is the alleged “intrinsic value” of nature—that is, the
alleged value of nature in and of itself, totally apart
from any connection to human life and well-being. Such
alleged intrinsic value is destroyed every time man
changes anything whatever in the preexisting state of
nature.
When the environmentalists speak of “harm to the
environment” in connection with such things as clearing
jungles, blasting rock formations, or the loss of this
or that plant or animal species of no known or
foreseeable value to man, what they actually mean in the
last analysis is the loss of the alleged intrinsic
values constituted by such things, and not any actual
loss whatever to man. On the contrary, they are eager to
sacrifice human life and well-being for the preservation
of such alleged intrinsic values. To them, the
“environment” is not the surroundings of man, deriving
its value from its relationship to man, but nature in
and of itself, deriving its value from itself—i.e.,
allegedly possessing “intrinsic” value.
Of course, the environmentalists also frequently pose as
supporters of human life and well-being, and at such
times they direct their fire at various comparatively
minor negative byproducts of production and economic
activity, such as local degradation of the quality of
air or water, while totally neglecting the enormous
positives, which, of course, are of overwhelmingly
greater significance.
What guarantees that the positive benefits of production
and economic activity incalculably outweigh any
negatives associated with their byproducts is the
principle of respect for individual rights. Although by
no means always observed, this principle requires that
one’s production and economic activity not only benefit
oneself but also that insofar as any other people are
involved in the process, the use of their labor and
property must be obtained only by their voluntary
consent. And, of course, to secure their voluntary
consent, their cooperation must be made worth their
while.
Thus, for example, if I wish to construct a building,
not only will I benefit from it, but also all those who
work for me in its construction and all those who supply
me with materials and equipment for constructing it. So
too will the building’s purchaser or tenants—if I
construct it for the purpose of sale or rent. In
addition, no third party’s property or person may be
harmed by my action. For example, I risk serious legal
penalty if I construct my building in a way that
undermines a neighboring building’s foundation or which
makes my building unsafe for passersby.
The major complaints the environmentalists currently
make concern the fact that I heat and air-condition my
building—to be sure, not I as one isolated individual,
but as one of many tens or hundreds of millions of
individuals using fossil fuels or CFCs. In so doing,
mankind is allegedly guilty of the crime of increasing
the level of carbon dioxide and other greenhouse gases,
thereby causing “global warming,” or increasing the
level of ozone-destroying molecules in the upper
atmosphere, thereby causing higher rates of skin cancer.
And because mankind is allegedly guilty in these ways,
the environmentalists assume that I as one individual
man must be restricted, if not prohibited altogether, in
my use of fossil fuels and CFCs, even though I, as one
individual, am utterly incapable of causing any of the
harmful effects alleged; and the same, of course, is
true, mutatis
mutandis, for each and every other
individual.
IV
Here I want to turn to the enormous spirit of
individualism that is found in von Mises. Only
individuals think and only individuals act, says von
Mises. It follows, of course, that it is only for his
own actions that an individual should be held
responsible. The son should not be punished for the sins
of the father; one member of a race or nation or
economic class should not be held responsible for the
deeds of any other members of that race, nation, or
economic class.
And so too should it be in the case of any alleged
environmental damage. If an individual, or an individual
business enterprise, is incapable by himself of causing
global warming or ozone depletion, or whatever, on a
scale sufficient to cause harm to any other specific
individual or individuals, then there is absolutely no
proper basis on the individualistic philosophy of von
Mises for prohibiting his action. As I say in
Capitalism,
“To prohibit the action of an individual in such a case
is to hold him responsible for something for which
he is
simply not in fact responsible. It is exactly the same
in principle as punishing him for something he did not
do" (p. 91).
The individual should not be punished for consequences
that can occur only as the result of the actions of the
broader category or group of which he is a member, but
do not occur as the result of his own actions. Thus,
even if it is true that the combined effect of the
actions of several billion people really is to cause
global warming or ozone depletion (neither of these
claims has actually been proven—the claims of global
warming have all the certainty of
a weather forecast,
extended out to the next 100 years!), but even
if, as I
say, the claims were true, it still would not follow
that any proper basis existed for prohibiting any
specific individual or individuals from acting in ways
that only when aggregated across billions of individuals
resulted in global warming or ozone depletion or
whatever.
If global warming or ozone depletion or whatever, really
are consequences of the actions of the human race
considered collectively, but not of the actions of any
given individual, including any given individual private
business firm, then the proper way to regard them is as
the equivalent of
acts of nature.
Not being caused by the actions of
individual
human beings, they are equivalent to actions not
morally
caused by human beings
at all,
that is to say, to
acts of nature.
Once we see matters in this light, it becomes clear what
the appropriate response is to such environmental
change, whether global warming and ozone depletion, or
global cooling and ozone enrichment, or anything else
nature may bring. It is the same as the appropriate
response of man to nature in general. Namely, individual
human beings must be free to deal with nature to their
own maximum individual advantage, subject only to the
limitation of not initiating the use of physical force
against the person or property of other individual human
beings. By following this principle, man will deal with
the any negative forces of nature resulting as
byproducts of his own activity taken in the aggregate in
precisely the same successful way that he regularly
deals with the primary forces of nature.
Allow me to elaborate on this. Here we are. We enjoy an
incredibly marvelous industrial civilization, whose
nature is indicated by the fact that because of it vast
numbers of human beings can travel at breathtaking
speeds for hundreds of miles at a stretch in their own
personal automobiles, listening to symphony orchestras
as they go—indeed, can fly over whole continents in a
matter of hours in jet planes, while watching movies and
drinking martinis; can walk into darkened rooms and
flood them with light by the flick of a switch; can open
a refrigerator door and enjoy delicious, healthful food
brought from all over the world; can do all this and so
much more. This is what we have. This, and much, much
more, is what people everywhere could have if they were
intelligent enough to establish economic freedom and
capitalism.
But all this counts for virtually nothing as far as the
environmentalists are concerned. They are ready to throw
it all away because, they allege, it causes global
warming and ozone depletion, i.e.,
bad weather.
And the best way, they say, for us to avoid such bad
weather, and thus to control nature more to our
advantage, is to abandon modern, industrial civilization
and capitalism.
The appropriate answer to the environmentalists is that
we will not sacrifice a hair of industrial civilization,
and that if global warming and ozone depletion really
are among its consequences, we will accept them and deal
with them—by such reasonable means as employing more and
better air conditioners and sun block, not by giving up
our air conditioners, refrigerators, and automobiles.
More fundamentally, the answer to the environmentalists
is that the appropriate response to environmental
change, whether global warming or a new ice age, is
the economic freedom
of a capitalist society. Sooner or later,
such environmental change will occur—if not in this new
century or even in this new millennium—then certainly at
some time in the more remote future. At that time, it
will require vast changes in human economic activity.
Some areas presently used for certain purposes will
become unuseable for those purposes. Conceivably, they
might even become uninhabitable. Other areas presently
uninhabitable or barely habitable, will become much more
desirable. Major changes in the comparative advantages
of vast areas will take place, to which people must be
free to respond.
As I wrote in
Capitalism,
Even if global warming turned out to be a fact, the free
citizens of an industrial civilization would have no
great difficulty in coping with it—that is, of course,
if their ability to use energy and to produce is not
crippled by the environmental movement and by government
controls otherwise inspired. The seeming difficulties of
coping with global warming, or any other large-scale
change, arise only when the problem is viewed from the
perspective of government central planners.
It would be too great a problem for government
bureaucrats to handle . . . . But it would certainly not
be too great a problem for tens and hundreds of millions
of free, thinking individuals living under capitalism to
solve. It would be solved by means of each individual
being free to decide how best to cope with the
particular aspects of global warming that affected him.
Individuals would decide, on the basis of
profit-and-loss calculations, what changes they needed
to make in their businesses and in their personal lives,
in order best to adjust to the situation. They would
decide where it was now relatively more desirable to own
land, locate farms and businesses, and live and work,
and where it was relatively less desirable, and what new
comparative advantages each location had for the
production of which goods. Factories, stores, and houses
all need replacement sooner or later. In the face of a
change in the relative desirability of different
locations, the pattern of replacement would be
different. Perhaps some replacements would have to be
made sooner than otherwise. To be sure, some land values
would fall and others would rise. Whatever happened
individuals would respond in a way that minimized their
losses and maximized their possible gains. The essential
thing they would require is the freedom to serve their
self-interests by buying land and moving their
businesses to the areas rendered relatively more
attractive, and the freedom to seek employment and buy
or rent housing in those areas.
Given this freedom, the totality of the problem would be
overcome. This is because, under capitalism, the actions
of the individuals, and the thinking and planning behind
those actions, are coordinated and harmonized by the
price system . . . . As a result, the problem would be
solved in exactly the same way that tens and hundreds of
millions of free individuals have solved much greater
problems, such as redesigning the economic system to
deal with the replacement of the horse by the
automobile, the settlement of the American West, and the
release of the far greater part of the labor of the
economic system from agriculture to industry. (pp.
88-89)
A rational response to the possibility of large-scale
environmental change is to establish
the economic freedom
of individuals to deal with it, if and when
it comes. Capitalism and the free market are the
essential means of doing this, not paralyzing government
controls and “environmentalism.” And both in the
establishment of economic freedom and in every other
major aspect of the response to environmentalism, the
philosophy of Ludwig von Mises and Carl Menger must lead
the way.
George Reisman is Pepperdine University Professor
Emeritus of Economics, and is the author of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics.
His website is
www.capitalism.net.
Copyright © 2001 by George Reisman. Permission is hereby
granted to reproduce and distribute this article
electronically and in print, other than as part of a
book.
(Email notification is
requested).
All other rights reserved.
This article, which draws on the author’s
Capitalism,
is an abridged version of his Mises Memorial Lecture,
delivered at the Ludwig von Mises Institute’s Austrian
Scholars’ Conference in 2001. A more abridged version
appeared in The
Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics,
vol. 5, no. 2. The present version was published as a
Daily Article
on
www.mises.org,
April 20, 2001, under the title “Environmentalism
Refuted.”
Labels:
A Free-Market Response to Global Warming,
Carl Menger,
collectivism,
individualism,
limitless potential of natural resources,
Ludwig von Mises,
production and economic activity improve the environment
Wednesday, May 23, 2007
The Arithmetic of Environmentalist Devastation
A major demand of the environmental movement, put
forward as essential to combating global warming, is the
imposition of a massive rollback in global emissions of
carbon dioxide accompanied by a freeze on such emissions
at the sharply reduced level imposed.
In this spirit, Britain’s
Stern Review,
published in the fall of 2006, seeks a reduction of 25
percent by the year 2050. Going considerably further,
the United Nations’ Intergovernmental Panel on Climate
Change has urged a 60 percent reduction.
Such pronouncements can be made openly and repeatedly
only because the immense majority of people do not take
the trouble to understand their implications. They do
not because what is required to do so is a combination
of making connections between various facts and
performing calculations. These are activities that are
widely perceived as onerous. Nevertheless, this level of
thinking is essential if people are to understand the
implications of environmentalism’s demands.
In purely verbal terms, those implications are that
environmentalism seeks the destruction of the energy
base of the modern world, along with the elimination or
radical reduction in the supply of all goods and
services that depend on that energy base. It seeks this
on the grounds that these goods and the energy on which
they depend entail the emission of carbon dioxide into
the atmosphere. The goods and services in question are
air conditioners, automobiles, airplane travel, housing,
food, clothing, refrigerators, freezers, television
sets, telephones, washers, dryers, books,
computers—everything that depends on the production and
use of oil, coal, or natural gas, which all release
carbon dioxide into the atmosphere in being burned. The
destruction of the energy base and the production of
goods and services is implied by the fact that in order
to rollback the emission of carbon dioxide, it is
necessary to rollback the production and use of energy
in these forms. But rolling back the production and use
of energy reduces the production of goods and services.
Turning now to the arithmetic of environmentalist
destruction, I will proceed to calculate the extent of
the reduction in carbon dioxide emissions per person
that is entailed in the environmentalist demands. This
will serve as a guide to the extent of the reduction in
the production and use of energy per person and thus as
a guide to the reduction in the production of goods and
services per person. Proceeding in this way, it will be
very easy to prove that environmentalism seeks the
destruction of the energy base of the modern world,
along with the elimination or radical reduction in the
supply of all goods and services that depend on it.
Let me start with the 25 percent reduction in global
carbon dioxide emissions urged by the
Stern Review.
Its application across the world would imply a 25
percent reduction in carbon dioxide emissions here in
the United States by 2050. Yet the population of the
United States in that year is projected to be
approximately 400 million people. Since the US
population is currently 300 million people, this means
that four-thirds of the present population of the US
would be expected to generate only three-fourths of
present carbon dioxide emissions. Three-fourths divided
by four-thirds is nine-sixteenths, or 56.25 percent.
That would be the projected
per capita
level of carbon dioxide emissions in the United States
in 2050, i.e., a reduction of 43.75 percent from today’s
level.
If the reduction in global carbon dioxide emissions is
to be 60 percent rather than 25 percent, then, with the
same increase in population, the reduction in per capita
emissions in the United States would be to a level found
by dividing 40 percent (the emissions remaining after
the 60 percent reduction) by four-thirds. Since division
by four-thirds is always multiplication by
three-fourths, the per capita reduction would be to a
level of 30 percent of today’s emissions instead of
56.25 percent. The per capita reduction in emissions in
the United States would be 70 percent rather than 43.75
percent.
But there is yet a further major reduction in US per
capita carbon dioxide emissions to contend with. And
that is that while global emissions will be reduced by
25 percent, or by 60 percent, emissions in China, India,
and the rest of the so-called third world will be
allowed to go on increasing, presumably until there is
equality in per capita emissions across the world.
At present, even though it has only 5 percent of the
world’s population, the US consumes 25 percent of the
world’s supply of energy and is responsible for
approximately 25 percent of the world’s carbon dioxide
emissions. Assuming the US population to remain at 5
percent of the world’s population, the achievement of
global equality in per capita carbon dioxide emissions
would require a reduction in US energy consumption from
its present 25 percent to 5 percent, corresponding to
the size of its population. This implies a further
reduction of 80
percent in per capita emissions in the US.
This is because 5 percent divided by 25 percent is 20
percent; a fall to 20 percent of the initial percentage
is a decline of 80 percent from the initial percentage.
This further decline of 80 percent in per capita carbon
dioxide emissions would apply to the already very
substantial percentage declines calculated above. Thus,
with a rollback of 25 percent in global emissions, the
decline in the US would be to 20 percent of 56.25
percent, i.e. to 11.25 percent. This, of course, would
be an 88.75 percent reduction in per capita US carbon
dioxide emissions. With a rollback of 60 percent in
global emissions, the decline in the US would be to 20
percent of 30 percent, i.e. to 6 percent. This would be
a 94 percent reduction in per capita US carbon dioxide
emissions.
Whether the per capita reduction in carbon dioxide
emissions is to 6 percent or to 11.25 percent, whether
or not a few percentage points of reduction can be
avoided by virtue of obtaining additional power from
windmills and solar panels (the environmentalists will
not allow atomic power, which they regard as the death
ray and oppose even more than carbon dioxide emissions,
nor will they allow hydro-power insofar as it interferes
with the migratory patterns of fish), the clear
implication is
economic devastation. It is devastation in
the production and use of energy and devastation in the
production of everything that depends on energy.
The implications of imposing environmentalism’s demands
include those that I have discussed in previous articles
on the subject. In terms of the life of individuals,
they are precisely of the kind described in the
newspaper articles I quote in
“After the Hideous
Light Bulbs.”
They also include such paradoxes as attempting to fight
global warming by means of destroying air conditioners,
refrigerators, and freezers. (I presented this
particular paradox in
“Environmentalist
Zen.”
That it is present in environmentalism is something that
should be glaringly obvious from the present article.)
It follows that inasmuch as anything may serve as an
opening wedge in getting people to accept
environmentalism’s agenda of destruction and
impoverishment, it needs to be opposed as strongly as
possible. Such is the case with the organized campaign
now underway to get people to accept the use of compact
fluorescent light bulbs in place of customary,
incandescent bulbs. As a prelude to their imposition by
law, the sale of these bulbs is currently being highly
subsidized by business firms seeking to curry favor with
environmentalists, in order to mitigate the harm that
they expect would otherwise be done to them. It should
be obvious that it is necessary to fight acceptance of
these bulbs, as I argue in
“Say No to the
Hideous Light Bulbs.”
There is tremendous public pressure today to join the
environmentalist cause. Business firms, that had long
opposed it are now rushing to join it. Opposition is
evaporating. Where there are still pockets of serious
resistance, environmentalist smears serve to undercut
their effectiveness. This has been the case, for
example, with respect to the British television
documentary
“The Great Global
Warming Swindle,”
which presents the views of numerous scientific experts
on climate and the causes of climate change who are
opposed to the environmentalists’ claim that global
warming is caused by carbon dioxide emissions.
The public embrace of a movement as dreadfully
destructive as environmentalism brings to mind the rush
to embrace Hitler and the Nazi Party in the Germany of
1932 and 1933, once their victory at the polls seemed to
become inevitable, and then once they actually came to
power. However the views of serious people, who hold
their views first-hand, based on their own, independent
judgment, do not change merely because the views of
others have changed.
Nazism was a catastrophe. Environmentalism has the
potential to be an even greater catastrophe—a far
greater catastrophe than Nazism: one that will result in
the deaths of billions rather than millions. This is
because it is the diametric opposite of economic
liberalism on a global scale. In contrast to liberalism
and its doctrine of the harmony of the rightly
understood self-interests of all men, environmentalism
alleges the most profound conflict of interests among
people. It implies that there is a major economic
benefit to be obtained through the death of billions of
fellow human beings, that, indeed, the well-being and
prosperity of the survivors depends on the extermination
of those billions.
Thus, for example, from the depraved perspective of
environmentalism, if global carbon dioxide emissions
equal to 25 percent of present emissions were to
disappear, because those responsible for them ceased to
exist, there would be no need for the global cutback in
emissions urged by the
Stern Review,
and thus no need for any diminution in economic
well-being on the part of the survivors (provided, of
course, their number did not increase). If still more
emissions could be eliminated by the elimination of
still more people, there would be room for actual
economic improvement among the survivors, according to
environmentalism. Obviously, the magnitude of mass
murder that is invited is the greater, the greater is
the alleged need to curb carbon dioxide emissions.
Those who recognize the astoundingly evil nature of
environmentalism must never cease opposing it.
This article is copyright © 2007, by George Reisman.
Permission is hereby granted to reproduce and distribute
it electronically and in print, other than as part of a
book and provided that mention of the author’s web site
www.capitalism.net
is included.
(Email notification is requested.)
All other rights reserved. George Reisman is the author
of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books, 1996) and is
Pepperdine University Professor Emeritus of Economics.
Labels:
Emissions Caps as a Cause of Global Conflict,
Environmentalism and impoverishment,
Industrial Civilization and Man-Made Power
Saturday, May 19, 2007
Environmentalist Bugaboo Loses Support
For years, the environmentalists have been trying to
have it both ways, claiming that in the midst of the
global warming that they allege, Europe might suffer an
ice age. According to this scenario, ships would sail
through an ice-free Arctic Ocean but be unable to unload
their cargos in the ice-bound ports of Northern Europe.
What was alleged to produce a European ice age at the
very time that the world as a whole was warming was the
destruction of the Gulf Stream, which brings warm water
from the Equator to the coast of Northern Europe.
Melting ice from the Arctic would allegedly overwhelm
the Gulf Stream and leave Europe defenseless against the
onslaught of frigid air streaming down from the Arctic,
the same frigid air that explains the much colder
climate of Eastern Canada. Eastern Canada lies at the
same latitude as Northern Europe but does not have the
benefit of the Gulf Stream.
Warmth from the Gulf Stream is necessary to keep Europe
temperate in the face of cold from the Arctic. It is not
necessary when the frigidity of the Arctic disappears.
The environmentalists chose not to recognize the
distinction. They took a position equivalent to that of
a deranged person, who possibly might confuse the
consequences of his not wearing his overcoat in July
with the consequences of his not wearing it in February.
It is one thing if the Gulf Stream were to disappear in
the climate conditions the world has become accustomed
to. It is something very different if it were to
disappear in the conditions of an Arctic so warm that
most of its ice melted.
The environmentalists and their stooges in the media
were not, and are not, concerned with logical
consistency. That requires holding the context and
making distinctions between different contexts. What
they are concerned with is whatever can be used to
strike fear in people: warming, freezing; flood,
drought; it’s all the same. If it provokes fear, their
tactic is to use it and play on it.
Well, this particular bugaboo may no longer serve. A
story in The New
York Times of May 15, 2007, titled
“Scientists Back Off
Theory of a Colder Europe in a Warming World”
explains why. (The story appears on p. F3 of
The Times’
Metropolitan Edition of the same date.)
The “backing off” is not based on any recognition of the
inherent contradictions in the argument, but on evidence
that the Gulf Stream is not easily destroyed and also is
not the only source of warming for Europe; prevailing
winds and other factors are now recognized as being more
important than the Gulf Stream.
Don’t expect this “backing off” to mean an actual
abandonment of claims of a European ice age. So long as
the world is full of people credulous enough to be
frightened by this story, environmentalists will
continue telling it.
This article is copyright © 2007, by George Reisman.
Permission is hereby granted to reproduce and distribute
it electronically and in print, other than as part of a
book and provided that mention of the author’s web site
www.capitalism.net
is included.
(Email notification is requested.)
All other rights reserved. George Reisman is the author
of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books, 1996) and is
Pepperdine University Professor Emeritus of Economics.
Labels:
Environmentalist bugaboo of European ice age in midst of
global warming.
Tuesday, May 15, 2007
Some New York Times’ Thoughts for the Day Concerning
Capitalism
From an article on urban development in India:
In an experiment that is highly unusual for this most
unplanned of countries, the government is doling out
money to Nagpur and other “second tier” cities to help
them modernize—fast.… Since its independence from
Britain in 1947, the city-building philosophy of India
has been, to put it gently, laissez-faire.—
“‘Second Tier’ City to Rise Fast Under India’s Urban
Plan.” (The article appears on p. 3 of the May 13,
Metropolitan Edition.)
The article’s use of the words “most unplanned of
countries” in reference to India is astonishing. India
is a country that for decades was perhaps the most
controlled and regulated country in the world outside
the Communist bloc and was in the forefront of state
“economic planning.” Yet the article ignores all this
and sees laissez-faire, not government interference, as
being India’s problem.
From an
article on land fraud in Utah:
“Excellent investment property in high-growth area,”
reads an eBay advertisement for the sale of 40 acres in
a remote part of rural Box Elder County. Good roads
(unencumbered by pavement), close to casinos (if 80
miles is close), and, the ad says, “Only one mile away
from Lucin Town.”
Ah, the lure of Lucin Town.
To reach Lucin from the pleasant county seat, Brigham
City, you must drive nearly 150 miles, around the top of
the Great Salt Lake and then southwest, along a two-lane
road curling past tumbleweeds and the very occasional
ranch. After a long while you turn left onto a dirt
road, travel six bumpy miles — and there you are, smack
in the middle of spectacular nothingness: Lucin.
Lucin is not even a ghost town; it is a ghost junction,
where lonely dirt road crosses lonely railroad track,
and the most prominent inhabitants are a snake, a beetle
and some large ants. Step on the parched earth to
examine that toppled Lucin sign, and dust kicks up.
These paragraphs, and the rest of the article in which
they appear, describe blatant fraud in the sale of land
in rural Utah. Fraud, of course, has nothing to do with
capitalism. It is against the law in a capitalist
society. Nevertheless, the article is titled
“Where Little Grows,
Capitalism Takes Root.”
(It appears on page 18 of the May 13, Metropolitan
Edition). What the title clearly implies is that such
fraud is part of capitalism.
The wider theme uniting both articles is that capitalism
is chaos, an “anarchy of production” in the words of
Marx, whose doctrines still live in the pages of
The New York Times.
Capitalism—laissez-faire—is allegedly chaos in urban
development. That’s claimed in the first article.
Capitalism is allegedly the chaos of fraud in land
sales. That’s the title of the second article.
Once again, the content of the paper’s news columns give
the lie to its claim that appears everyday on page 2,
that its “news
and editorial departments do not coordinate coverage.”
They do, perhaps not by conscious design, but by shared
philosophy and Marxist economic theory. Almost all of
the writers, reporters, and editors of the paper come
from the same educational mold and see practically
everything through a far-left prism, with the result
that The Times’
reporting is thoroughly slanted to the left. It is not a
vehicle for the impartial reporting of the news, but a
vehicle for leftist propaganda.
Copyright © 2007 by George Reisman.
Labels:
capitalism,
laissez-faire
Sunday, May 13, 2007
The Scandalous Student Loan Scandal
The student loan scandal concerns the fact that many
colleges and universities chose preferred lenders for
financing student loans and then received remuneration
for their recommendations from the lenders. The scandal
has been going on since mid-March. Thus, it is startling
to learn that it was not until April 30 that any
evidence was provided concerning how anyone might have
been harmed by the practice.
The New York
Times of May 1
reports
that Pratt Institute, a New York college of art and
design, had temporarily entered into an arrangement in
which a lender was charging students a rate of interest
of 15 percent, a rate supposedly far above that
available elsewhere. Apparently on its own, the school
cancelled the arrangement and stopped recommending the
lender. The lender had not given any compensation to
Pratt but had instead agreed to “provide grant money for
needy students.” (The article also appears on p. A17 of
The Times’
Metropolitan Edition.)
“Details of the arrangement, and its cancellation,”
The Times
informed its readers, “were disclosed yesterday [April
30] by Pratt and Attorney General Andrew M. Cuomo of New
York.” The Times
then went on to state that “Pratt’s findings that its
students were being charged such high interest rates are
the first
evidence to emerge from Mr. Cuomo’s inquiry
showing how students could have suffered from
undisclosed arrangements between universities and
lenders that the attorney general has branded a conflict
of interest.” (My italics.)
The meaning of this is that we had the spectacle of a
public scandal going on for over a month
without any evidence
to justify it.
If one thinks about it, there is no difference in
principle between a college or university receiving
compensation from lenders that it recommends and
compensation from dining halls and bookstores that it
recommends. (There are undoubtedly many cases in which
campus dining halls and bookstores are not owned or
operated by the schools whose students they serve. Yet
their location on campus serves as an extremely powerful
recommendation of them by the school. The schools, of
course, derive income from these establishments.)
And just as in those cases, the compensation to the
school should normally be expected to derive from the
lower costs of operation for the suppliers that the
recommendations make possible, not from higher prices to
customers, in this case, interest rates to students.
This may not always be the case, as in the
above-mentioned instance of Pratt Institute, but it is
certainly very often the case, and probably is the case
most of the time. This is because the preferred lenders
enjoy reduced marketing expenses, for example.
Similarly, the dining halls and bookstores benefit from
the greater volume of business the school’s
recommendation gives them, and consequently they have
lower unit costs.
In all such instances, the recipients of the school’s
recommendation have no need to charge more. They are in
a position to share with the school part of the
additional profits resulting from lower costs. Moreover,
exercise of the most elementary degree of
conscientiousness on the part of the school would
normally serve to guarantee that charges to its students
were competitive. Indeed, in order to be sure of
capturing the volume of business that their preferred
position and consequent lower costs opens up to them,
preferred providers will often find it to their interest
to charge less
than most others. Charging lower prices or interest
rates is the means by which their lower costs translate
into a competitive advantage over other suppliers.
Finally, competition from firms not recommended always
serves to strictly limit what can be charged by those
who receive the recommendations. There is no more reason
to prohibit schools from recommending lenders on the
grounds that students will be charged higher interest
rates than there is to prohibit them from recommending
dining halls and bookstores on the grounds that these
establishments will charge higher prices for the meals
and textbooks that they sell. The student’s simple and
obvious safeguard in all such cases is to look at what
others are charging. If semester after semester it does
not occur to a student to do this, then perhaps he is
simply not qualified for college.
What is present in the schools’ receipt of payments for
their recommendations is nothing other than the normal
workings of an economic system that is based on the
profit motive and trade to mutual advantage. When one
party benefits another, he should normally expect
payment in return. That is all that is present here.
And, as I’ve indicated, contrary to the expectations of
The New York
Times and its reporters, and of most
government officials, profits and the profit motive, in
combination with competition, do not serve to make goods
more expensive but
less
expensive.
It is difficult to resist the conclusion that what is
actually being complained of in this instance and in so
many others is the fact that under capitalism a supplier
works for his own profit and is not the sacrificial
slave of the buyer. It is ironic that in the present
case, the victims of this anti-capitalistic attitude are
colleges and universities. What is ironic is that they
systematically instill such anti-capitalistic attitudes
in practically every course they offer. There is thus a
measure of justice in the fact that in this instance
their teachings have been put to use against them.
This article is copyright © 2007 by George Reisman.
Permission is hereby granted to reproduce and distribute
it electronically and in print, other than as part of a
book and provided that mention of the author’s web site
www.capitalism.net
is included.
(Email notification is requested.)
All other rights reserved. George Reisman is the author
of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books, 1996) and is
Pepperdine University Professor Emeritus of Economics.
Labels:
The scandalous student loan scandal.
Saturday, May 12, 2007
If you’d prefer to be cool rather than suffer in the
heat, what you need to do, according to the
environmental movement, is smash your air conditioner,
refrigerator, and freezer. That will help to cool the
planet—someday. If you want to be secure from
hurricanes, floods, tornadoes, and other natural
(according to it, manmade) disasters, what you need to
do is destroy the energy base required to produce and
operate modern construction equipment and means of
transportation. In that case you may end up living in a
thatched hut and have only a donkey to go from one place
to another, but the absence of man-made power and its
carbon emissions will make the world such a tame and
happy place that you won’t need anything more. After
all, natural disasters are not caused by nature, which
is wonderful, pure, and benign, but by us! Remember that
as you listen to the sound of one hand clapping.
Copyright © 2007, by George Reisman.
Labels:
Environmentalism and impoverishment,
Environmentalist Zen
Tuesday, May 08, 2007
After the Hideous Light Bulbs
In my last article, I urged everyone to say no to the
hideous looking fluorescent light bulbs the
environmentalists plan to force on us in the name of
fighting global warming and “saving the planet.” I
described the light bulbs as an entering wedge for
further demands adding up to the sacrifice of our entire
standard of living.
Here’s the kind of demands the environmentalists have in
store to follow our acceptance of the light bulbs, if we
should be so foolish.
Give Up
Clothes Dryers and Power Lawn Mowers
From The
International Herald Tribune, February 23,
2007, p. 2:
In most of Europe and North America, when we wash our
clothes—and we wash them a lot—people frequently toss
the load into an energy-eating tumble dryer.… Largely
because of this habit, a T-shirt in its lifetime will
require the use of 1,400 grams, or 50 ounces, of fuel,
produce 450 grams of waste that goes to landfill and
send 4 kilograms, or 9 pounds, of carbon dioxide into
the atmosphere, according to a recent Cambridge
University study. If the owner were to wash that T-shirt
in warm (40 degrees Celsius, 104 Fahrenheit) rather than
hot (60 degrees Celsius) water, and hang it out to dry,
the carbon dioxide emissions created by that shirt
would be reduced by 85 to 90 percent.
An average-power lawn mower produces as much emissions
in an hour as eight cars going 89 kilometers, or 55
miles, per hour. Use a manual mower.
So get ready to say goodbye to power lawn mowers and to
clothes dryers. Be assured that washing machines and
countless other things will follow. The article in
question itself describes many other sacrifices,
including containers for hot cups of coffee and
cardboard packaging. The author appears to think she’d
get by just as well carrying her coffee everywhere in
her own mug. And she lauds Zurich, where “people carry
their new televisions home without a box: naked
appliances, delivered in the most eco-friendly package.”
Give Up Fresh
Hot Water and Central Heating
On January 6, 2007,
The New York Times
published an article titled
“The Land of Rising
Conservation,”
which I previously
commented on in this
blog.
The theme of the article was that Japan is the model
country of energy conservation, pointing the way for the
United States on the basis of the use of the latest
technology. Indeed, the subtitle of the article, in the
print edition, was “Japan Offers a Lesson in Using
Technology to Lessen Energy Consumption.” Here is what
the article had to say on the subjects of fresh hot
water and central heating:
Mr. Kimura says he, his wife, and two teenage children
all take turns bathing in the same water, a common
practice here. Afterward, the still-warm water is sucked
through a rubber tube into the nearby washing machine to
clean clothes. Wet laundry is hung outside to dry or
under a heat lamp in the bathroom.
The different approach is also apparent in the layout of
Mr. Kimura’s home, which at 1,188 square feet is about
the average size of a house in Japan but only about half
as big as the average American one. The rooms are also
small, making them easier to heat or cool. The largest
is the living room, which is about the size of an
American bedroom.
During winter, the entire family, including the
miniature dachshund, gathers here, which is often the
only room heated. Like most Japanese homes, Mr. Kimura’s
does not have central heating. The hallways, stairwell
and bathrooms are left cold. The three bedrooms have
wall-mounted heaters, which are used only when the rooms
are occupied, and switched off at night.
The living room is kept toasty by hot water running
through pipes under the floor. Mr. Kimura says such
ambient heat saves money. He says the energy bill for
his home is about 20,000 yen ($168) a month. Central
heating alone would easily double or triple his energy
bill, he says.
“Central heating is just too extravagant,” says Mr.
Kimura, who is solidly middle class.
The government has tried to foster a culture of
conservation with regular campaigns like this winter’s
Warm Biz, a call to businesspeople to don sweaters and
long johns under their gray suits so that office
thermostats could be set lower.
In other words, in addition to bathing in other people’s
bathwater and then washing your clothes in it, expect to
freeze in winter. And you should also expect to end up
in a house the size of those in Japan, or smaller.
Whatever you do, be sure to remember that Mr. Kimura is
“solidly middle class.” Otherwise you might think that
he’s pathetically poor and that you will be too if you
have to reduce your energy consumption to his level.
Give Up
Toilet Paper, Elevators, and Most of the Rest of the
Modern World
On April 23, Cheryl Crow, the well-know singer was
quoted in Britain’s
The Register
as saying: "I propose a limitation be put on how many
squares of toilet paper can be used in any one sitting.
Now, I don't want to rob any law-abiding American of his
or her God-given rights, but I think we are an
industrious enough people that we can make it work with
only one square per restroom visit, except, of course,
on those pesky occasions where two to three could be
required."
Ms. Crow has reportedly since claimed that she was
merely joking. Be that as it may, her proposal follows
logically from ideas that permeate the environmental
movement. It follows from the belief in the need to
reduce consumption as a means of reducing the emission
of carbon dioxide into the atmosphere, which emissions
allegedly cause global warming. It also follows from the
doctrine of the alleged intrinsic value of nature
undisturbed by man. If the trees from which toilet paper
is ultimately made are intrinsically valuable and thus
must not be disturbed, it follows that man should not
have toilet paper.
As a result, it is not surprising that opposition to the
use of toilet paper has appeared elsewhere, and in the
even more extreme form of a total cessation of its use,
and that it has been accompanied by a very wide, almost
general rejection of the goods of modern capitalism,
including elevators, freezers, television sets, and
much, much more. This rejection is the subject of the
recent New York
Times article
“The Year Without
Toilet Paper”
(Metropolitan Edition, March 22, 2007, p. F1).
The article is about a well-to-do, well-connected young
couple living on lower Fifth Avenue in New York City and
currently dedicating their lives to achieving “No
Impact” on their environment. To be sure their
motivation may at least partly be to promote the
husband’s forthcoming book on the subject. But such
would not be the motivation of the book’s readers, who
presumably will want to learn for themselves how live
without making an impact on the environment. And it does
not seem to be the major part of their motivation
either. For example, the wife is quoted as saying that
after she saw Al Gore’s movie “An Inconvenient Truth,”
she “`felt like everything I did in my life was
contributing to a system that was really problematic.…
If I was a student, I would march against myself.’”
I must quote at length from the article to show the
scope of what this couple has given up in the name of
their environmentalist philosophy:
DINNER was the usual affair on Thursday night in
Apartment 9F in an elegant prewar on Lower Fifth
Avenue.… A visitor avoided the bathroom because she knew
she would find no toilet paper there.… Meanwhile,
Joseph, the liveried elevator man who works nights in
the building, drove his wood-paneled, 1920s-era vehicle
up and down its chute, unconcerned that the couple in 9F
had not used his services in four months.
Welcome to Walden Pond, Fifth Avenue style.… Colin
Beavan, 43, a writer of historical nonfiction, and
Michelle Conlin, 39, a senior writer at Business Week,
are four months into a yearlong lifestyle experiment
they call No Impact. Its rules are evolving, as Mr.
Beavan will tell you, but to date include eating only
food (organically) grown within a 250-mile radius of
Manhattan; (mostly) no shopping for anything except said
food; producing no trash (except compost, see above);
using no paper; and, most intriguingly, using no
carbon-fueled transportation.…
Since November, Mr. Beavan and [his two-year old
daughter] Isabella have been hewing closely, most
particularly in a dietary way, to a 19th-century life.…
right now that means
lots of apples and root vegetables, stored in the
unplugged freezer…Olive oil and vinegar are out; they
used the last dregs of their bottle of balsamic vinegar
last week.… The television, a flat-screen,
high-definition 46-incher, is long gone…. The dishwasher
is off, along with the microwave, the coffee machine and
the food processor. Planes, trains, automobiles and that
elevator are out, but the family is still doing laundry
in the washing machines in the basement of the building.
(Consider the ramifications of no-elevator living in a
vertical city: one day recently, when Frankie the dog
had digestive problems, Mr. Beavan, who takes Isabella
to day care—six flights of stairs in a building six
blocks away—and writes at the Writers Room on Astor
Place—12 flights of stairs, also six blocks
away—estimated that by nightfall he had climbed 115
flights of stairs.) And they have not had the heart to
take away the vacuum from their cleaning lady, who comes
weekly (this week they took away her paper towels).…
Toothpaste is baking soda.… (Nothing is a substitute for
toilet paper, by the way; think of bowls of water and
lots of air drying.)
This is the kind of life implied by environmentalism and
its demands for limits on carbon dioxide emissions. If
total, global emissions are fixed, while population
increases, per capita emissions must necessarily
decline, and along with them the energy production that
gives rise to them and the products whose production and
use depend on that energy production. If, in addition,
emissions in today’s third-world countries increase,
those in first world countries must decrease, with the
result of a further per capita decline in the first
world countries. Add to that the effect of progressive
reductions in the volume of global emissions until they
are merely a fraction of what they were in the year 2000
or 1990, which is what the environmentalists want to
achieve, and there can be no other outcome but the most
radical decline in the standard of living of the first
world countries. Thus, if the environmentalists have
their way, one can expect to personally experience the
kind of deprivations described in the various news
stories presented above.
Such a life of impoverishment is a life that the
environmentalists who are striving to bring it about
certainly deserve to achieve—but just for themselves,
not for anyone else.
This article is copyright © 2007, by George Reisman.
Permission is hereby granted to reproduce and distribute
it electronically and in print, other than as part of a
book and provided that mention of the author’s web site
www.capitalism.net
is included.
(Email notification is requested.)
All other rights reserved. George Reisman is the author
of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books, 1996) and is
Pepperdine University Professor Emeritus of Economics.
Labels:
destruction of energy production and of industrial
civilization,
Environmentalism and impoverishment
Thursday, May 03, 2007
Say No to the Hideous Light Bulbs
The
environmentalists are pushing hideous looking
fluorescent light bulbs of the kind shown here as a way
to save electricity and thus reduce the need for power
plants and resulting carbon emissions. The bulbs will
thus allegedly help to save the planet from global
warming and, therefore, the environmentalists argue,
everyone should use them instead of the customary,
incandescent bulbs.
Australia and Canada have already enacted laws or
regulations that will make these bulbs mandatory within
a few years. Efforts are underway to do the same thing
here in the United States.
In fact, my local power company is currently subsidizing
the sale of these bulbs in Southern California
supermarkets. Normally, $7.99 apiece, my local power
company makes it possible to buy them in packs of three
for just $1.
I confess. At that low price my curiosity got the better
of me and I bought a pack. I even temporarily installed
one of the bulbs in my garage, to see what kind of light
it provided.
I concluded that I wouldn’t be comfortable doing any
sustained reading under it, simply because the light it
gives off doesn’t seem quite right. Otherwise though,
the bulb clearly does have some uses, at least in
situations in which appearance is not an important
consideration. For example, it might be used in
commercial storage facilities and locations in business
offices given over to holding old files. Homeowners with
unfinished garages that display bare studs and flex and
perhaps an occasional indelible oil stain on the floor,
who regard their garages merely as storage areas and/or
workplaces, may find that they too are an appropriate
setting for the bulb. In such garages, the bulb doesn’t
need to express the owner’s normal aesthetic
preferences. It would probably fit in perfectly with
such things as steel storage shelves, assorted tools,
boxes and crates, old rags, and stray items hanging from
hooks and nails banged into a wall.
My question is, though, how could anyone want such a
thing in his
home, in his living room, bedroom, or dining
room, or anywhere else that one is supposed to
live
rather than change oil or make repairs or, of course,
just leave one’s car.
My point here is that to bring these bulbs inside one’s
house, as the environmentalists are urging everyone to
do, requires that people be prepared to give up the
aesthetic qualities of their homes and, in effect, spend
their lives living in the equivalent of their garages
(or the garages that many others have).
If you wouldn’t mind an oil stain in the middle of your
living room carpet, wall studs visible through gaps in
your home’s drywall, steel storage shelves in your
bedroom, and tools, boxes, and crates lying here and
there—or if this is the way you already live—then these
bulbs are for you. You should buy them. Over the years,
they’ll save you some money on your electric bills and
you won’t need to change them as often as you have to
change conventional light bulbs.
But if you don’t want to live in the equivalent of a
garage, if the extra cost of living in a normal home is
worth it to you, then you should definitely not bring
these bulbs into your home. Indeed, you should react
with outrage at any suggestion that you should. Because
what you’re being asked to do is
turn your home into a
dump.
The environmentalists want you to turn your home into a
dump “for the sake of the planet” by helping to “avoid
global warming.” That’s supposed to justify it. Tell
them it doesn’t.
They want you to agree to live in a dump, because if
they can do that, they will have succeeded in making you
define yourself as not worthy of anything better. And
once, they’ve accomplished that, they can go on to
demand any further sacrifice they may want to impose on
you.
Not so long ago, people were being told throughout the
length and breadth of the former Soviet Union that they
had to live in dumps and sacrifice any hope of material
prosperity for themselves because it was necessary to
build up the means of production of their socialist
society, from which their grandchildren would benefit.
And then, when the grandchildren came of age, they in
turn were told that they needed to sacrifice for the
sake of their
grandchildren.
People finally got tired of this orgy of unending
sacrifice and overthrew the Communists.
Unfortunately, it hasn’t taken very long for the concept
of human sacrifice to revive and come back stronger than
ever. The light bulbs are a profoundly important
symbolic first step. They are an entering wedge for the
environmentalists’ demand that we sacrifice our entire
standard of living—variously, for the sake of the
“planet,” for the sake of the countries of the Third
World, and for the sake of assorted species of animals
and plants. And unlike with the Communists, the
sacrifice is now presented not as temporary but
explicitly as a new, permanent way of life.
So tell them again:
No sacrifice.
Not for “the planet,” not for the Third World, not for
other species. Tell them your life belongs to you and
you mean to enjoy it. Tell them that the planet exists
for you, not you for the planet, and that you intend to
use it for your benefit.
This article is copyright © 2007, by George Reisman.
Permission is hereby granted to reproduce and distribute
it electronically and in print, other than as part of a
book and provided that mention of the author’s web site
www.capitalism.net
is included.
(Email notification is requested.)
All other rights reserved. George Reisman is the author
of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books, 1996) and is
Pepperdine University Professor Emeritus of Economics.
Thanks to Chad Parish of the Mises Institute for the
graphic.
Labels:
Environmentalism and impoverishment,
hideous light bulbs
Return to Top of
Page
|