What Is
Interventionism?*
By
George Reisman**
Interventionism is any act of government that both represents the
initiation of physical force and, at the same time, stops short of
imposing an all-round socialist economic system, in which production takes
place entirely, or at least characteristically, at the initiative of the
government. In contrast to socialism, interventionism is a system in which
production continues to take place characteristically, at the initiative
of private individuals, including private corporations, and is motivated
by the desire to earn private profit. Interventionism exists in the
framework of a market economy, though, as von Mises puts it, such a
market economy is a hampered market economy.
Many
countries often thought to be socialist, either now or in the past, such
as Sweden, Israel, and Britain under the old Labor Party, should be
thought of as hampered market economies instead. For production in those
countries characteristically takes place, or did take place, at private
initiative, motivated by private profit. The effect of the very extensive
interventionism in those countries was or is to prevent people from doing
many, many things they would have done had they been free to do them and
to compel them to do many, many things they would not have done had they
not been compelled to do them. But within those confines, matters
pertaining to production were and are characteristically still decided by
private individuals, motivated by the prospect of making profits and
avoiding losses. Thus, it is still private initiative, motivated by
private profit, that animates and drives the economy of those countries.
The fact that the ruling political party in such countries may call itself
socialist and support the philosophy of socialism is not sufficient to
make them socialist countries in fact.
The only
genuinely socialist countries that have existed have been the Soviet Union
and its East European satellites, Communist China and its satellites,
Cuba, and also, very importantly, Nazi Germany. Mises explains that Nazi
Germany was a socialist state by virtue of the existence of all-round
price controls and the consequent shortages they create. In response
to the existence of shortages and the economic chaos that accompanies
them, the government takes control of all fundamental decisions concerning
production, such as what is produced, in what quantities, by what methods,
and who is to get the resulting product. Mises call such socialism,
socialism on the German or Nazi pattern, to distinguish it from the
obvious socialism of the Soviets, in which all means of production are
openly nationalized, and which he calls socialism on the Russian or
Bolshevik pattern.
Socialism on
the German pattern is deceptive and often mistakenly characterized as
capitalism because it maintains the outward form and appearance of private
ownership of the means of production and thus of capitalism. However,
under German-style socialism, private ownership exists in name only. The
power to make all the substantive decisions that constitutes the essence
of ownership is in the hands of the government and is exercised by the
government. Socialism on the German or Nazi pattern is de facto
socialism.
Hopefully,
the distinction between interventionism and socialism is now clear.
However, it
is also necessary to distinguish interventionism from proper, legitimate
government action, which does not represent interventionism.
All
government action, good and bad, represents the use of physical force.
There is an expression in Latin, "nulla lege sine poena"—which
means, in translation, "there is no law without punishment."
Every law, edict, ruling, decree, or regulation that a government issues
is backed by the threat of physical force—even to the point of killing
whoever does not obey it. And this applies even to the most minor
offenses, such as refusal to wear a seat belt or to pay a parking ticket.
First may come reminder letters, increasingly less polite, asking for
payment of the initial fine. If they are ignored, then may come greater
fines. Beyond the fines comes the threat of arrest and imprisonment. And
if, when the officers come to make the arrest, one resists, then whatever
force is required to overcome one's resistance will be applied, including
the use of firearms and sharpshooters.
Now by no
means is it the case that all such instances are wrong, unreasonable, or
in any way objectionable. There are murderers, muggers, rapists, robbers,
and con men of various types (the activity of these last is
tantamount to robbery). The deeds of all these categories of people
represent the use of physical force, in that they constitute physically
doing something to or with the person or property of another against his
will. More than that, such actions represent the initiation of
physical force. When the government uses force against such perpetrators,
its actions represent the use of physical force in defense or retaliation,
on behalf of innocent victims.
The
government's use of force in such cases, provided it is not excessive, is
entirely appropriate. In essence, it is the same as the physical force
used by the Sheriffs and United States Marshals, depicted in old Western
movies, against bank robbers, cattle rustlers, and so on. The difference
between the use of physical force in defense or retaliation and the
initiation of physical force is the essential difference between the guys
in the white hats and the guys in the black hats in those Western movies.
It's the difference between the physical force used by a bank robber and
the bank guard, the physical force used by a kidnapper and the physical
force used by the rescuers of the kidnapper's victim.
Exactly the
same point applies to a country's armed forces. They are a legitimate use
of force insofar as they are used in defense and retaliation against
foreign aggression.
The
government's use of defensive and retaliatory force does not represent
interventionism. In such cases, the government is simply doing its
entirely proper, strictly limited job of protecting individual rights from
the initiation of physical force. The concept of interventionism applies
only to instances in which the government uses physical force not in a
defensive or retaliatory capacity, but as an aggressor, that is,
uses physical force against people who have not initiated its use.
This is what
the government does every time it forbids any voluntary, contractual
relationship, such as the offer and acceptance of a price or wage, or
products or working conditions, that the parties judge to be in their
respective self-interest to offer and accept. Likewise, the government
initiates the use of physical force whenever it compels one man to pay any
part of his wealth or income, against his will, for the benefit or
support of another, as is the case in the financing of public welfare,
public housing, and public education, or for some alleged benefit to
himself that he prefers not to pay for, such as a future Social Security
or Medicare benefit.
So much for
the nature of interventionism. The policy of the strict avoidance of
interventionism is the policy of laissez-faire, which, very simply,
is to be understood as: if it—that is, the action or situation or
whatever—does not represent the initiation of physical force, the
government must leave it alone, i.e., not intervene.
Now we must
turn to the question of what precisely is the scope of interventionism.
This is a question that is very closely related to the further question of
what is the cost of interventionism.
One method
of judging the scope of interventionism, at least as a first
approximation, is to consider the number of Federal Cabinet Departments
and the various alphabet agencies that now exist and judge how many of
them would remain, and to what extent, if the guiding principle were
enacted that the government is not to initiate the use of physical force,
and thus end all of its intervention, i.e., if the guiding principle were laissez-faire.
At present,
three are fifteen Cabinet Departments: Agriculture, Commerce, Defense,
Education, Energy, Health and Human Services, Homeland Security, Housing
and Urban Development, Interior, Justice, Labor, State, Transportation,
Treasury, and Veterans' Affairs. The best known of the alphabet agencies
are probably the IRS, the FRB and FDIC, the EPA, FDA, SEC, CFTC, NLRB,
FTC, FCC, FERC, NRC, FAA, CAA, INS, OHSA, CPSC, NHTSA, EEOC, BATF, DEA,
NIH, NASA, CIA, and FBI.
If the
government were to be restricted to the use of force only in defense or
retaliation, the only Cabinet Departments that would remain would be
Justice—to prosecute acts of initiation of force across state lines and
possible acts of aggression by State governments—Defense, State, and
Treasury. All others would be eliminated. (This would essentially reduce
the number of Cabinet Departments to the original five that existed under
Washington. The Department of Defense incorporates what were then, and
until as recently as 1948, the separate Departments of War and Navy.)
Of course,
not even these Departments would continue as they are presently
constituted. For example, the Justice Department would lose its Antitrust
Division, which would be closed, and the Treasury Department would lose
the IRS, which would also be closed. The Department of Defense would be
scaled back to defending only the territory of the United States and
abandon the mission of acting as global policeman. The State
Department would cease to grant foreign aid.
As for the
alphabet agencies, probably only the FBI would survive, and its area of
investigation would be limited exclusively to acts entailing the
initiation of physical force across state lines or against the United
States.
The scope
and also the cost of interventionism can be judged by considering the
current budget of the Federal Government and the magnitude and makeup of
the expenditures of the state and local governments. The Federal Budget
for the current fiscal year of 2003 projected total Federal outlays of
$2140 billion. Of that sum only $364.6 billion appeared under the
heading "National defense," $25.4 billion under the heading
"Homeland Security," and $18.3 billion under the heading
"Justice." For the reasons explained, of course, these sums
would be substantially less under a policy of strict laissez-faire.
But even taking them at their stated levels, it is clear that the
overwhelming bulk of government spending, i.e., all but the $408.3 billion
that comes under these three headings combined, out of the $2140 billion
overall total, is spending that represents government intervention,
spending that would not exist under laissez faire. Such
spending at the Federal level is clearly in excess of 80%, and may well be
close to 90%, of total Federal spending. The elimination of this spending
would make possible the abolition of the personal and corporate
income taxes and the inheritance and capital gains taxes, along with the
special taxes to pay for Social Security, Medicare, and Medicaid.
The
situation is essentially the same with respect to the spending of state
and local governments. In the first quarter of this year state and local
government spending, according to the statistics published by the
government's own Bureau of Economic Analysis, was running at an annual
rate in excess of $1410 billion. Of this sum, no more than 15-20% is
classified under the heading of "Public Order or Public Safety."
Since the
states and localities currently receive almost $313 billion of the funds
they expend from the Federal Government, and that sum is already included
under Federal spending, the total of government spending going to
individuals and businesses comes to $3237 billion rather than $3550
billion.
To place
this sum in perspective, it should be compared with the total of incomes
earned, i.e., so-called national income, which is reported as currently
running at an annual rate of $8445 billion. This figure, it should
be noted is substantially inflated by so-called imputations, i.e.,
monetary allowances for economic activity that does not earn money. An
example is the imputation for the net rental income allegedly received by
homeowners in renting their homes to themselves. Removing these
imputations would reduce national income substantially—probably by at
least 10%, which would put it at approximately $7600 billion.
Indeed, this
figure must be further substantially reduced. National income currently
includes approximately $1028 billion of wages and salaries paid to
government employees. To appraise the impact of government spending on the
taxpayers who must pay for it, most of those wages and salaries must be
deducted from the reported national income figure—all of them except the
portion which itself is paid in as taxes, which is probably no more than a
third, at the utmost. Thus, we now have an adjusted national income figure
of roughly $6911 billion, which reflects the subtraction of $689 billion
of after-tax wages of government employees. From this, one should also
subtract approximately $218 billion of net interest paid by the Federal
Government, which is counted in National Income. When this is done, the
National Income in the hands of the taxpayers and on which the burden of
government falls, comes out as $6693 billion. It is this figure against
which the impact of $3237 billion of government spending must
be judged. As a percentage of this figure, government spending amounts to
approximately 48%! This is an enormous burden, one that is far higher than
usually reported.
But this is
by no means the full story. This is merely a measure of the direct
cost of government spending. What the government does with the money it
spends can impose enormous additional costs. For example, this year's
Federal budget lists an expenditure of $7.6 billion as the budget of the
Environmental Protection Agency, which is charged with enforcing and
applying existing environmental legislation and enacting all manner of new
and additional regulations authorized by the legislation under which it
operates. This agency is the one that decides what air and water quality
standards must be met, and which species are endangered. Its use of
whatever billions have been budgeted for it over the years has undoubtedly
served to impose many hundreds of billions, possibly several
trillions, of dollars of additional costs on businesses and consumers
across the country.
Indeed, such
indirect costs should be assumed to be the result of all of
the regulatory agencies. As the result of OSHA, the Occupational Health
and Safety Administration, CPSC, the Consumer Product Safety Commission,
and NTSB, the National Transportation Safety Board, the prices of many
consumers’ goods have been substantially increased in order to comply
with government-mandated safety requirements. In at least one case, that
of stepladders, the price has been more than doubled. The FDA—the Food
and Drug Administration—substantially adds to the costs of new drugs to
whatever extent it unnecessarily delays their introduction. Indeed, it
causes people to suffer and die unnecessarily by preventing the
introduction of drugs that have already proved their value for many years
in other countries. The FTC—i.e., the Federal Trade Commission—along
with the Antitrust Division of the Department of Justice, routinely
prevents business firms from achieving greater economies by preventing
them from carrying out mergers that would reduce costs and thus prices.
The NLRB—the National Labor Relations Board—routinely drives up
business costs and prices by compelling collective bargaining with labor
unions and thus the payment of union scales and acceptance of union work
rules. At the same time, of course, it adds to unemployment, because at
the higher wage rates it causes, the quantity of labor demanded is
necessarily reduced in comparison to what it would be in a free labor
market. And, perhaps worst of all, the Federal Reserve Board
systematically inflates the money supply of the country, thereby causing
all of the serious problems that result from inflation, including periodic
recessions and the potential for major deflation and depression.
Such extra
costs are in the very nature of interventionism. As we have seen, to the
extent that there is interventionism, individuals are prohibited from
taking peaceful actions they judge to be in their interest and/or are
compelled to take actions they judge to be against their interest. A
leading category of actions that individuals judge to be in their interest
are those that make it possible for them to achieve better results and
lower costs. The actions they seek to avoid are those that will cause them
to achieve poorer results and incur higher costs. By preventing
individuals from doing what is in their interest to do and compelling them
to do what is against their interest to do, it is not surprising that
interventionism succeeds in holding back improvement and driving up costs.
I believe
that the growing cost of interventionism is what is responsible for the
fact that apart from the contribution made by women working more, real
income for large numbers of working families in the United States has been
stationary or even declining over the last thirty years or more.
A major vice
of interventionism is that it tends to grow. In the words of Mises,
"Prior Intervention Breeds Later Intervention." For example, the
government imposes rent controls. The result is that private investors
don’t want to build rental housing, because it isn’t profitable.
Instead of repealing the rent controls, the government goes on to build
public housing, claiming that the free market has failed.
Or it
imposes rate regulation on the railroads and at the same time inflates the
money supply, compels the railroads to deal with the railway unions, and
subsidizes massive highway construction. The result: lack of profitability
in railroading and declining investment and quality and service in that
industry, all adding up to another alleged failure of the free market and
consequent alleged need to nationalize an industry.
The same
pattern is now being repeated with respect to privately owned electric
utilities, whose rates are controlled, while inflation drives up their
costs, and who are prevented by the environmental movement from building
even such additional facilities as they are able to build to keep pace
with growth in demand, and who are then blamed for the resulting power
shortages.
Or, the
government imposes minimum-wage and prounion legislation, thereby
compulsorily pricing workers out of the market and into unemployment. Then
the complaint is made that capitalism suffers from an inherent problem of
unemployment, necessitating a system of public welfare and government
job-creation programs.
Or, the
government imposes medical licensing, which keeps down the supply of
physicians and artificially increases their rates, making their services
unaffordable by people who otherwise could have afforded them. Then, in an
effort to alleviate this problem, it encourages employer-financed medical
"insurance" so-called, which has the effect of making the cost
of medical care seem virtually free to growing numbers of workers. This is
a system which should be understood not as any actual kind of insurance,
but as the collectivization of medical costs. Because of the lack
of cost of medical care to the individual under this arrangement, the
demand for medical services begins to grow without limit.
Physicians
cash in on the system by ordering more and more tests and procedures that
may be of some benefit to their patients, but which they would not have
ordered if they knew the patients themselves would have to pay for them
and could not afford to do so. Soon physicians become exposed to
malpractice suits for failing to order such tests and procedures and even
for taking a patient’s financial circumstances into account at all. They
then begin practicing "defensive medicine," ordering still more
tests and procedures in order to protect themselves from such suits. And
malpractice insurance premiums grow ever higher.
In this
process, the cost of medical care is driven beyond the reach of more and
more people who lack so-called medical "insurance." To deal with
this problem, the government goes on to establish the programs of
"Medicare" and "Medicaid." The effect of these
programs is to drive up the costs of medical care still further and to
expose anyone who remains outside the system of so-called medical
"insurance" to financial ruin should he need any significant
medical care.
Finally, in
order to limit the rise in costs, the government more and more seizes
control of what doctors and hospitals are allowed to do and how they are
to do it. This is the point we are at today in medical care.
In addition
to their economic cost, it should be realized that many if not all of the
administrative agencies that carry out the various interventionist
programs routinely violate basic protections of Anglo-Saxon law. This is
because they combine within themselves the role of legislator, executive,
prosecutor, judge, and jury. The regulations they enact take effect upon
publication in The Federal Register, whereupon they are added to
the Code
of Federal Regulations, which now contains several tens
of thousands of pages. The regulations have the force of law and are often
unintelligible, vague, arbitrary, or contradictory.
It would be
very valuable for a volume, or, better, a series of volumes, to be written
someday, perhaps titled "Alphabet Soup or the Cost and Consequences
of Federal Regulations," which would detail the harm done by
each and every government regulatory agency and each and every improper
Cabinet department. Naturally, the same thing would have to be done at the
level of state and local governments.
Such a
project, should, of course, also deal with the intellectual foundations of
interventionism, that is, the ideas and arguments, the doctrines and
theories, that underlie it in each case, and with its intellectual sources
in the writings of such figures as Marx and Keynes and Robinson and
Chamberlin.
The role of
Marx is especially noteworthy. His exploitation theory underlies the
assumption that interventionism has no cost to anyone but the capitalist
"exploiters"—that it somehow just comes out of "surplus
value" or profits. This notion, that government intervention is
costless to its alleged beneficiaries is powerfully reinforced by the
government’s ability to create money, which makes its expenditures
appear costless to the citizens, whose taxes do not have to be immediately
increased to pay for additional government spending when that spending can
be paid for by the government out of newly created money.
The ultimate
goal of this project, of course, would be nothing less than the
elimination of all government intervention and thereby the achievement of
a fully free and far more rapidly progressing and prosperous society than
we have today. Its main inspiration would be the works of Ludwig von
Mises, the careful reading and studying of which by large numbers of
scholars would be the most important prerequisite for its undertaking.
Along these
lines, perhaps as a section in the Introduction to such an undertaking,
I’d like to offer what I believe would be a pro-free-market,
anti-poverty program. That is, a program for alleviating poverty not
by means of additional government intervention, which has been the
standard formula for so long that people seem to have lost the ability
even to imagine any alternative, but by means of the repeal of
existing government intervention and corresponding enlargement of the
sphere of economic freedom.
I want to
explain what sorts of things might be done, based on the principle of
abolishing government intervention and enlarging economic freedom, to make
it possible for low-paid workers to earn more money than they now do and
to keep more of what they earn, and also what kinds of things might be
done, again based on the principle of abolishing government intervention
and enlarging economic freedom, that would serve to make housing, medical
care, and goods in general more affordable by poor people. Based on a
combination of higher incomes and lower prices, poverty can certainly be
greatly reduced, if not eliminated altogether.
To increase
the incomes of poor people, the first thing that must be done is to
abolish laws that prevent them from working and thus from earning income.
The leading example of this type of law is the minimum-wage law, which
forces people into unemployment and thereby deprives them both of the
income they might earn by working and of the opportunity of gaining
work experience and quite possibly of developing work skills that would
later on enable them to perform more valuable work and thus earn more than
they could presently earn.
Abolition of
the minimum-wage law and the resulting employment of more workers at lower
wage rates would serve both to reduce costs of production and to increase
the supply of goods and services produced in the economic system, both of
which in turn would serve to reduce prices. Previously unemployed poor
people would thus both earn more money and be able to buy goods and
services at lower prices than were possible before.
Of course,
those poor people who were lucky enough to have jobs at the minimum wage
would now be earning lower wages. To some extent, those lower wages would
be offset by lower prices, which would come about on the foundation of
the repeal of the minimum-wage law, as we have just seen. To the extent
that the lower wages would not be offset by lower prices, there is a
free-market remedy—in the form of the repeal of prounion and licensing
legislation.
Such
legislation is essentially similar to minimum-wage legislation. It is
minimum-wage legislation for semi-skilled and skilled labor. Like
minimum-wage legislation, its purpose is to forcibly impose wage rates
above the level that a free labor market would establish. And just like
minimum-wage legislation, it reduces the quantity of labor demanded below
the supply available and thus causes unemployment.
The only
difference is that the unemployed workers in these cases are not totally
deprived of employment. They have alternative employment opportunities.
Displaced from the occupations in which they would have worked in a free
labor market, they can still turn to other, less desirable jobs. Thus, for
example, unemployed carpenters, electricians, and plumbers can seek work
in factories, restaurants, or other establishments. Their influx into such
other lines of work, however, serves to enlarge the supply of labor in
those other lines. This larger supply of labor is employable only at lower
wage rates than would have prevailed in the absence of the influx of
labor.
To this
extent, the effect of prounion and licensing legislation, it should be
observed, is to raise the wage rates of some workers only by
correspondingly reducing the wages rates of other workers, and, at the
same time, of course, reducing the supply of more valued goods and
services and increasing the supply of less valued goods and services in
the economic system. The effect is tantamount to the wiping out of a
portion of human skills and abilities.
If wage
rates in the lines of work to which the displaced workers turn are
prohibited from falling, because they too are unionized, the displaced
workers may still find work, insofar as their relatively superior
abilities enable them to outcompete other, less qualified workers in those
lines. In such cases, there is a further displacement of labor into less
desirable jobs. The process of displacement may go through several stages.
A minimum-wage law serves to make it end in unemployment plain and simple,
with the least-skilled, least educated bearing the brunt of it.
Repealing
prounion and licensing legislation at the same time as minimum-wage
legislation were repealed would reverse this process. At the same time
that previously unemployed workers entered the labor market at the bottom
of the economic ladder, other workers previously employed at the bottom
would be leaving, to move up to the higher-level jobs which their skills
and abilities qualified them for and from which prounion and licensing
legislation had previously barred them. The result would be that wage
rates at the lower levels would not have to fall as much as they would if
only minimum-wage legislation had been repealed.
In such
circumstances, there would be an increase in the supply of labor at all
levels of skill and ability in the economic system, a resulting general
fall in money wage rates, and in costs of production, and a general
increase in the supply of goods and services, accompanied by a general
fall in prices.
The greatest
gainers from this process would be the poor, especially those of them
who previously had been unemployed. They would now be employed at the
least possible fall in wage rates, and the fall in wage rates would be
accompanied by a fall in prices almost certainly greater than the fall in
the wage rates of those members of the poor lucky enough to already have
had jobs.
The fall in
prices would be greater than the fall not only in their wage rates but
also in the overall average of wage rates. This is implied in the fact
that the supply of labor employed is not only larger but is also now
employed in ways that better take advantage of the skills and abilities of
the workers, that is, in ways in which their overall productivity is
higher.
The rise in
the productivity of labor is manifested in part in the expansion of the
production of more valued goods and services at the expense of the
production of less valued goods and services. This in itself implies an
increase in the supply of products greater than the increase in the supply
of labor employed and thus, in the face of unchanged monetary demands for
labor and products, a fall in prices greater than the fall in wages.
The rise in
the productivity of labor and consequent increase in the supply of
products in greater proportion than the increase in the supply of labor,
and thus a fall in product prices in greater proportion than the fall in
wage rates, results especially from the abolition of prounion legislation.
Such legislation enables the unions to prevent or delay the introduction
of labor-saving machinery, to prevent or minimize competition among
workers, and to impose arbitrary and costly work rules and outrageous
featherbedding practices, all of which signify a lower productivity of
labor and thus a lower supply of products relative to the supply of labor,
and thus higher product prices relative to wage rates. Take away this
interference, and prices fall relative to wage rates, i.e., real wages
rise.
In addition,
and very important, the end of large-scale unemployment that would be
achieved by a free labor market would further serve to raise real wage
rates by eliminating the burden that wage earners must bear in supporting
the unemployed, either through voluntary contributions to help unemployed
friends or relatives or through the payment of taxes to support
unemployment compensation and public welfare.
A further
source of a rise in real wage rates would be the abolition of the
government’s Social Security and Medicare programs. This would have the
potential of directly increasing workers’ take-home wages in excess of
15 percent, inasmuch as so-called employer contributions for these
programs are already part of the employers’ labor costs and could be
passed on to the workers in the form of higher take-home wages.
Yet a
further rise in real take-home wages would be achieved if workers were
given the option of withdrawing from employer-financed health insurance
programs and having the employer contributions paid to them directly, as
tax-free wages instead of, as at present, being a tax-free fringe benefit.
This change, as I will later show, would also be an important step in
bringing about a radical reduction in the cost of medical care.
If
interventionism is not eliminated in the ways I have described, and in
other ways that I have not yet described, or at least very substantially
reduced, then it will be necessary to place special focus on its
elimination in other aspects of the restraints it places on people
working. While a free economy makes it possible for real wages to rise to
ever higher levels and thus to progressively reduce the amount of work
required to achieve any given level of living standard, i.e., to both
reduce the hours of work and increase the age at which work begins, an
economic system characterized by growing government intervention requires
the opposite outcome, if people are not to be utterly impoverished. That
is, it requires that people work longer hours and start work at a younger
age, in order to produce enough to meet both the voracious demands of the
government and their own vital needs. In other words, to prevent
interventionism from driving growing numbers of people into abject
poverty, it becomes necessary at some point that maximum-hours and
child-labor legislation become a major target of efforts at repeal.
Maximum-hours
and child-labor legislation are especially sacred cows of interventionism,
because of the widely held belief that the amount of work that workers
perform affects employers’ profits rather than workers’ wages. The
basis of this idea is the Marxian exploitation theory, which holds that
wages in a free market are determined by the number of hours of labor
required to produce the average worker’s minimum subsistence, and that
hours of labor performed in excess of that number serve merely to enlarge
employers’ profits. Based on this utterly fallacious idea, people
believe that the compulsory shortening of the working day serves merely to
reduce profits, not wages, and that the prohibition of child labor has the
same effect.
The truth,
of course, is that wages are not determined by minimum subsistence but by
the demand for and supply of labor. And while a larger supply of labor
serves to reduce hourly wage rates, its performance also correspondingly
increases the supply of consumers’ goods and thus serves to reduce the
prices of consumers’ goods. Assuming unchanged demands for labor and
consumers’ goods and an unchanged output per unit of labor, the fall in
average hourly wage rates resulting from any given percentage increase in
the supply of labor hours must be accompanied by a corresponding fall in
the prices of consumers’ goods. And because the workers who work the
extra hours are able to offset the fall in hourly wage rates by means of
their extra hours, they benefit from their extra work in the form of lower
prices of the things they buy.
In other
words, a longer working day and starting work at a younger age do serve to
raise real wages, and, by the same token, a shorter working day and
starting work at a later age do serve to reduce real wages. In a free
market, the progressive rise in the output per unit of labor—the
productivity of labor—which occurs because of the work of
scientists and inventors and the work and saving of businessmen and
capitalists, brings about a progressive fall in prices relative to wage
rates and thus a progressive rise in real wage rates. It is this which
permits the progressive shortening of hours and elimination of child labor
that characterizes a free market. Growing government intervention in
contrast, throws this process into reverse. And then, because of the
prevailing ignorance of economics, just as the interventionists claimed
undeserved credit for the shortening of hours and elimination of child
labor achieved by the free market, the advocates of economic freedom will
be subjected to undeserved criticism for urging the repeal of such
legislation in order to mitigate the consequences of growing
interventionism.
My
discussion of ways to increase the money incomes of poor people has been
inextricably intertwined with discussions of the prices they must pay and
what would serve to reduce those prices. This has been unavoidable,
because real wages are determined by prices as much as they are by money
wages, and thus there is simply no way intelligently to discuss wages
without discussing prices.
I now want
to indicate some major specific ways in which the prices or costs that
poor people pay could be reduced by means of reducing or abolishing
government intervention. Of course, these same price and cost reductions
will be of benefit to everyone who buys the goods or services concerned.
Let’s
start with medical care. I’ve already said that a major step in bringing
about a radical reduction in the cost of medical care would be to have
employer contributions to employee medical insurance paid to workers
directly, as tax-free income. Making individuals financially responsible
for their own medical care would reintroduce powerful buyer resistance to
further increases in the cost of medical care and equally powerful
pressure for actual decreases in the cost of medical care.
To bring
down the absurdly bloated costs of the present system, it would be
necessary to enlarge the sphere of economic freedom in some important
additional ways as well. One essential way would be to establish freedom
of competition among hospitals. Even without totally doing away with the
present restrictive system of licensing, if it were made possible for,
say, any three already licensed physicians to establish their own
hospital, specializing in whatever procedures they cared to specialize in,
from relatively simple appendectomies and tonsillectomies to quadruple
bypass operations and the removal of brain tumors, hospital rates would
soon be dramatically reduced.
This is
because the present rates of $2000 per day or more far exceed the
necessary costs of providing their services. Free competition in hospitals
would drive their rates down toward their necessary costs plus only as
much profit as required to yield a competitive rate of profit. And it
would also operate progressively to reduce those costs, while improving
the quality of the services provided, just as it does throughout the rest
of the economic system. All the costs of unnecessary paperwork and of
compliance with endless arbitrary government regulations could be
eliminated, as well as requirements to subsidize nonpaying patients.
An essential
requirement of bringing down costs would be respecting the freedom of
contract of hospitals and patients to opt out of the standards of
malpractice that have developed in recent decades and to choose to be
guided by earlier and more reasonable standards. The same freedom of
contract concerning malpractice standards should, of course, be applied to
the relationship between patient and physician, and any and all laws or
government regulations preventing physicians from offering discounted
rates to uninsured patients should be abolished. Allowing physicians not
to report fees from uninsured patients on their income tax returns would
likely be extremely helpful.
These
measures would go a long way toward making medical care affordable by
individuals choosing to receive as take home wages the premiums presently
paid by employers to medical insurers.
Let us turn
now to how the cost of housing could be reduced for poor people. Laws and
regulations imposing minimum housing standards, such as those concerning
minimum size of apartments and minimum window areas have the effect of
imposing standards that are often too high for poor people to afford. They
are comparable to a law that in the name of safety or reducing air
pollution would prohibit automobiles over a certain age from using the
public streets or highways. Since the older cars are less expensive, they
are precisely the kind of cars that poor people tend to own. And the
effect of such a law would therefore be largely to prohibit poor people
from driving. In exactly the same way, laws prohibiting poorer quality
housing, which is precisely the kind of housing that poor people can
afford, serves to deprive poor people of housing. Laws and regulations
prohibiting unrelated adults from sharing living quarters have the same
effect. I’m convinced that all such laws and regulations bear
responsibility for the phenomenon of homelessness.
The
withdrawal of land from development by environmental regulations makes
land scarcer and more expensive and thus serves to raise the cost of
providing housing. Zoning laws, which arbitrarily increase minimum lot
sizes and limit the height of buildings have the same effect.
Government-imposed building-safety codes, delays in granting permits, and
laws and regulations supporting the higher wage rates and restrictive work
practices of the construction unions, also serve to raise the cost of
housing, as do property taxes and anything that holds back saving. (Saving
is the foundation of housing construction and mortgage credit. The greater
is the supply of savings relative to the demand for consumers’ goods,
the lower are interest rates, including mortgage rates, and thus the lower
is the cost of housing, including rental housing. I will say more in a
little while about how government interference undermines saving and
capital accumulation throughout the economic system.)
Protective
tariffs and farm subsidies must be mentioned as important causes of prices
being higher and thus real wages being lower than they need to be. And
since poor people can least afford such reductions in real wages, they are
their worst victims. Poor people are the worst victims of government
intervention in general, because they can least afford the resulting
inefficiencies and rise in costs and prices.
And this
brings me to a wider point. Namely, it needs to be understood that the
main way, the only significant way, in which poverty is eliminated is by
means of the rise in the productivity of labor. This is what raises real
wages, by increasing the supply of consumers goods relative to the supply
of labor and correspondingly reducing prices relative to wage rates.
The rise in
the productivity of labor in turn is based on capital accumulation.
Capital accumulation is what places in the hands of the average worker the
tools, machines, materials, and previously produced products of all kinds
that make possible the rise in his productivity. Capital accumulation is
itself based on the combination of a sufficiently high degree of saving
and provision for the future relative to current consumption, and
scientific and technological progress. It both makes possible the
progressive adoption of more advanced technologies and is itself sustained
by their adoption, which makes possible a growing production of more and
better goods, including further capital goods.
A major
aspect of saving and provision for the future relative to current
consumption is that it determines the demand for labor relative to the
demand for consumers’ goods and thus the height of wages relative to
profits. The greater is saving and provision for the future relative
to current consumption, the higher are wages relative to profits.
Deeper even
than saving and capital accumulation and scientific and technological
progress is economic freedom and respect for private property rights. The
security of property is essential for people to be motivated to save and
invest. To save and invest, they must know that what they save and invest
will be theirs and not be seized by the government or by other private
individuals. Economic freedom is further essential to capital accumulation
and economic progress because it is the precondition of businessmen and
capitalists not only saving and investing but also making the most
efficient use of all existing means of production. The larger is the
output obtained from existing means of production, the larger is not only
the production of consumers’ goods but also of further capital goods.
The results of any given degree of saving and provision for the future are
correspondingly greater and the accumulation of capital is made
correspondingly easier and greater.
Such
taxes as the progressive income tax, the corporate income tax, and
the inheritance and capital gains taxes greatly impair the ability to save
and accumulate capital. They are paid largely with funds that otherwise
would have been saved and productively expended, i.e., expended for
capital goods or labor by business firms. Instead, those funds are
expended by the government, or by those to whom the government gives the
money, for consumers’ goods. The effect is to reduce the demand for
capital goods relative to the demand for consumers’ goods and thus the
production of capital goods relative to the production of consumers’
goods. This is a sure formula for reducing or preventing capital
accumulation or causing capital decumulation.
Government
budget deficits, the Social Security system, and inflation of the money
supply produce similar negative effects on capital accumulation. Budget
deficits draw savings away from business investment and into financing the
consumption expenditure of the government. The Social Security system
leads private individuals to save less, both by depriving them of the
income needed for saving and by leading them to believe that their and
their employers’ taxes paid into the system are savings for the future.
Meanwhile, the government consumes those taxes.
Inflation of
the money supply undermines capital accumulation by leading to a
systematic overstatement of profit and interest incomes and corresponding
increases in the taxation of such incomes, while simultaneously raising
the replacement prices of capital goods. The result is that business firms
lack adequate funds for replacement. At the same time, the overstatement
of profit and interest incomes and the paper capital gains caused by
inflation promotes consumption by private individuals, who are led to
believe that they are richer merely because inflation has raised their
money incomes and the prices of their assets. Inflation of the money
supply undermines capital accumulation in further ways as well, which I
will discuss in my session on "The Economics of Inflation."
Interventionism
in all of its forms serves to undermine capital accumulation and thus the
productivity of labor and real wages. It does so insofar as it serves to
reduce the output of the economic system, because a major portion of that
output is capital goods, and thus what reduces output reduces the
production of capital goods no less than the production of consumers’
goods, and thereby makes capital accumulation correspondingly more
difficult or impossible.
In
conclusion, interventionism reduces the standard of living of everyone,
but its impact on the poor, who can least afford any reduction in their
standard of living, is necessarily greatest. If one wants to overcome
poverty, there is only one essential means of doing so. And that is the
establishment of economic freedom to the fullest possible extent, i.e.,
the establishment of laissez-faire capitalism.
The wider
and more fundamental principle is that the foundation of economic
prosperity is economic freedom.
This article originally appeared on web
site of the Ludwig von Mises Institute on September 10, 2003
*Copyright
© 2003 by George Reisman. All rights reserved.
**George
Reisman, Ph.D., is professor of Economics at Pepperdine University’s
Graziadio School of Business and Management and is the author of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books,
1996).
Return to Top of
Page
|