Why Nazism Was Socialism and Why Socialism Is
Totalitarian
by George
Reisman
[Posted
on the website of the Ludwig von Mises Institute, Friday,
November 11, 2005]
My
purpose today is to make just two main points: (1) To show
why Nazi Germany was a socialist state, not a capitalist
one. And (2) to show why socialism, understood as an
economic system based on government ownership of the means
of production, positively requires a totalitarian
dictatorship.
The identification of Nazi Germany as a socialist state was
one of the many great contributions of Ludwig von Mises.
When one remembers that the word "Nazi" was an abbreviation
for "der Nationalsozialistische Deutsche Arbeiters
Partei — in English translation: the National Socialist
German Workers' Party — Mises's identification might not
appear all that noteworthy. For what should one expect the
economic system of a country ruled by a party with
"socialist" in its name to be but socialism?
Nevertheless, apart from Mises and his readers, practically
no one thinks of Nazi Germany as a socialist state. It is
far more common to believe that it represented a form of
capitalism, which is what the Communists and all other
Marxists have claimed.
The basis of the claim that Nazi Germany was capitalist was
the fact that most industries in Nazi Germany appeared to be
left in private hands.
What Mises identified was that private ownership of the
means of production existed in name only under the
Nazis and that the actual substance of ownership of the
means of production resided in the German government. For it
was the German government and not the nominal private
owners that exercised all of the substantive powers of
ownership: it, not the nominal private owners, decided
what was to be produced, in what quantity, by what methods,
and to whom it was to be distributed, as well as what prices
would be charged and what wages would be paid, and what
dividends or other income the nominal private owners would
be permitted to receive. The position of the alleged private
owners, Mises showed, was reduced essentially to that of
government pensioners.
De facto government ownership of the means of
production, as Mises termed it, was logically implied by
such fundamental collectivist principles embraced by the
Nazis as that the common good comes before the private good
and the individual exists as a means to the ends of the
State. If the individual is a means to the ends of the
State, so too, of course, is his property. Just as he is
owned by the State, his property is also owned by the State.
But what specifically established de facto
socialism in Nazi Germany was the introduction of price and
wage controls in 1936. These were imposed in response to the
inflation of the money supply carried out by the regime from
the time of its coming to power in early 1933. The Nazi
regime inflated the money supply as the means of financing
the vast increase in government spending required by its
programs of public works, subsidies, and rearmament. The
price and wage controls were imposed in response to the rise
in prices that began to result from the inflation.
The effect of the combination of inflation and price and
wage controls is shortages, that is, a situation in
which the quantities of goods people attempt to buy exceed
the quantities available for sale.
Shortages, in turn, result in economic chaos. It's not only
that consumers who show up in stores early in the day are in
a position to buy up all the stocks of goods and leave
customers who arrive later, with nothing — a situation to
which governments typically respond by imposing rationing.
Shortages result in chaos throughout the economic system.
They introduce randomness in the distribution of supplies
between geographical areas, in the allocation of a factor of
production among its different products, in the allocation
of labor and capital among the different branches of the
economic system.
In the face of the combination of price controls and
shortages, the effect of a decrease in the supply of an item
is not, as it would be in a free market, to raise its price
and increase its profitability, thereby operating to stop
the decrease in supply, or reverse it if it has gone too
far. Price control prohibits the rise in price and thus the
increase in profitability. At the same time, the shortages
caused by price controls prevent increases in supply from
reducing price and profitability. When there is a shortage,
the effect of an increase in supply is merely a reduction in
the severity of the shortage. Only when the shortage is
totally eliminated does an increase in supply necessitate a
decrease in price and bring about a decrease in
profitability.
As a result, the combination of price controls and shortages
makes possible random movements of supply without any effect
on price and profitability. In this situation, the
production of the most trivial and unimportant goods, even
pet rocks, can be expanded at the expense of the production
of the most urgently needed and important goods, such as
life-saving medicines, with no effect on the price or
profitability of either good. Price controls would prevent
the production of the medicines from becoming more
profitable as their supply decreased, while a shortage even
of pet rocks prevented their production from becoming less
profitable as their supply increased.
As Mises showed, to cope with such unintended effects of its
price controls, the government must either abolish the price
control or add further measures, namely, precisely the
controls over what is produced, in what quantity, by what
methods, and to whom it is distributed, which I referred to
earlier. The combination of price controls with this further
set of controls constitutes the de facto
socialization of the economic system. For it means that the
government then exercises all of the substantive powers of
ownership.
This was the socialism instituted by the Nazis. And Mises
calls it socialism on the German or Nazi pattern, in
contrast to the more obvious socialism of the Soviets, which
he calls socialism on the Russian or Bolshevik pattern.
Of course, socialism does not end the chaos caused by the
destruction of the price system. It perpetuates it. And if
it is introduced without the prior existence of price
controls, its effect is to inaugurate that very chaos. This
is because socialism is not actually a positive economic
system. It is merely the negation of capitalism and its
price system. As such, the essential nature of socialism is
one and the same as the economic chaos resulting from the
destruction of the price system by price and wage controls.
(I want to point out that Bolshevik-style socialism's
imposition of a system of production quotas, with incentives
everywhere to exceed the quotas, is a sure formula for
universal shortages, just as exist under all around price
and wage controls.)
At most, socialism merely changes the direction of the
chaos. The government's control over production may make
possible a greater production of some goods of special
importance to itself, but it does so only at the expense of
wreaking havoc throughout the rest of the economic system.
This is because the government has no way of knowing the
effects on the rest of the economic system of its securing
the production of the goods to which it attaches special
importance.
The requirements of enforcing a system of price and wage
controls shed major light on the totalitarian nature of
socialism — most obviously, of course, on that of the German
or Nazi variant of socialism, but also on that of
Soviet-style socialism as well.
We can start with the fact that the financial self-interest
of sellers operating under price controls is to evade the
price controls and raise their prices. Buyers otherwise
unable to obtain goods are willing, indeed, eager to pay
these higher prices as the means of securing the goods they
want. In these circumstances, what is to stop prices from
rising and a massive black market from developing?
The answer is a combination of severe penalties combined
with a great likelihood of being caught and then actually
suffering those penalties. Mere fines are not likely to
provide much of a deterrent. They will be regarded simply as
an additional business expense. If the government is serious
about its price controls, it is necessary for it to impose
penalties comparable to those for a major felony.
But the mere existence of such penalties is not enough. The
government has to make it actually dangerous to conduct
black-market transactions. It has to make people fear that
in conducting such a transaction they might somehow be
discovered by the police, and actually end up in jail. In
order to create such fear, the government must develop an
army of spies and secret informers. For example, the
government must make a storekeeper and his customer fearful
that if they engage in a black-market transaction, some
other customer in the store will report them.
Because of the privacy and secrecy in which many
black-market transactions can be conducted, the government
must also make anyone contemplating a black-market
transaction fearful that the other party might turn out to
be a police agent trying to entrap him. The government must
make people fearful even of their long-time associates, even
of their friends and relatives, lest even they turn out to
be informers.
And, finally, in order to obtain convictions, the government
must place the decision about innocence or guilt in the case
of black-market transactions in the hands of an
administrative tribunal or its police agents on the spot. It
cannot rely on jury trials, because it is unlikely that many
juries can be found willing to bring in guilty verdicts in
cases in which a man might have to go to jail for several
years for the crime of selling a few pounds of meat or a
pair of shoes above the ceiling price.
In sum, therefore, the requirements merely of enforcing
price-control regulations is the adoption of essential
features of a totalitarian state, namely, the establishment
of the category of "economic crimes," in which the peaceful
pursuit of material self-interest is treated as a criminal
offense, and the establishment of a totalitarian police
apparatus replete with spies and informers and the power of
arbitrary arrest and imprisonment.
Clearly, the enforcement of price controls requires a
government similar to that of Hitler's Germany or Stalin's
Russia, in which practically anyone might turn out to be a
police spy and in which a secret police exists and has the
power to arrest and imprison people. If the government is
unwilling to go to such lengths, then, to that extent, its
price controls prove unenforceable and simply break down.
The black market then assumes major proportions.
(Incidentally, none of this is to suggest that price
controls were the cause of the reign of terror instituted by
the Nazis. The Nazis began their reign of terror well before
the enactment of price controls. As a result, they enacted
price controls in an environment ready made for their
enforcement.)
Black market activity entails the commission of further
crimes. Under de facto socialism, the production and sale of
goods in the black market entails the defiance of the
government's regulations concerning production and
distribution, as well as the defiance of its price controls.
For example, the goods themselves that are sold in the black
market are intended by the government to be distributed in
accordance with its plan, and not in the black market. The
factors of production used to produce those goods are
likewise intended by the government to be used in accordance
with its plan, and not for the purpose of supplying the
black market.
Under a system of de jure socialism, such as existed in
Soviet Russia, in which the legal code of the country openly
and explicitly makes the government the owner of the means
of production, all black-market activity necessarily entails
the misappropriation or theft of state property. For
example, the factory workers or managers in Soviet Russia
who turned out products that they sold in the black market
were considered as stealing the raw materials supplied by
the state.
Furthermore, in any type of socialist state, Nazi or
Communist, the government's economic plan is part of the
supreme law of the land. We all have a good idea of how
chaotic the so-called planning process of socialism is. Its
further disruption by workers and managers siphoning off
materials and supplies to produce for the black market, is
something which a socialist state is logically entitled to
regard as an act of sabotage of its national economic plan.
And sabotage is how the legal code of a socialist
state does regard it. Consistent with this fact,
black-market activity in a socialist country often carries
the death penalty.
Now I think that a fundamental fact that explains the
all-round reign of terror found under socialism is the
incredible dilemma in which a socialist state places itself
in relation to the masses of its citizens. On the one hand,
it assumes full responsibility for the individual's economic
well-being. Russian or Bolshevik-style socialism openly
avows this responsibility — this is the main source of its
popular appeal. On the other hand, in all of the ways one
can imagine, a socialist state makes an unbelievable
botch of the job. It makes the individual's life a
nightmare.
Every day of his life, the citizen of a socialist state must
spend time in endless waiting lines. For him, the problems
Americans experienced in the gasoline shortages of the 1970s
are normal; only he does not experience them in relation to
gasoline — for he does not own a car and has no hope of ever
owning one — but in relation to simple items of clothing, to
vegetables, even to bread. Even worse he is frequently
forced to work at a job that is not of his choice and which
he therefore must certainly hate. (For under shortages, the
government comes to decide the allocation of labor just as
it does the allocation of the material factors of
production.) And he lives in a condition of unbelievable
overcrowding, with hardly ever a chance for privacy. (In the
face of housing shortages, boarders are assigned to homes;
families are compelled to share apartments. And a system of
internal passports and visas is adopted to limit the
severity of housing shortages in the more desirable areas of
the country.) To put it mildly, a person forced to live in
such conditions must seethe with resentment and hostility.
Now against whom would it be more logical for the citizens
of a socialist state to direct their resentment and
hostility than against that very socialist state itself? The
same socialist state which has proclaimed its responsibility
for their life, has promised them a life of bliss, and which
in fact is responsible for giving them a life of
hell. Indeed, the leaders of a socialist state live in a
further dilemma, in that they daily encourage the people to
believe that socialism is a perfect system whose bad results
can only be the work of evil men. If that were true, who in
reason could those evil men be but the rulers
themselves, who have not only made life a hell, but have
perverted an allegedly perfect system to do it?
It follows that the rulers of a socialist state must live in
terror of the people. By the logic of their actions and
their teachings, the boiling, seething resentment of the
people should well up and swallow them in an orgy of bloody
vengeance. The rulers sense this, even if they do not admit
it openly; and thus their major concern is always to keep
the lid on the citizenry.
Consequently, it is true but very inadequate merely to say
such things as that socialism lacks freedom of the press and
freedom of speech. Of course, it lacks these freedoms. If
the government owns all the newspapers and publishing
houses, if it decides for what purposes newsprint and paper
are to be made available, then obviously nothing can be
printed which the government does not want printed. If it
owns all the meeting halls, no public speech or lecture can
be delivered which the government does not want delivered.
But socialism goes far beyond the mere lack of freedom of
press and speech.
A socialist government totally annihilates these
freedoms. It turns the press and every public forum into a
vehicle of hysterical propaganda in its own behalf, and it
engages in the relentless persecution of everyone who dares
to deviate by so much as an inch from its official party
line.
The reason for these facts is the socialist rulers' terror
of the people. To protect themselves, they must order the
propaganda ministry and the secret police to work 'round the
clock. The one, to constantly divert the people's attention
from the responsibility of socialism, and of the rulers of
socialism, for the people's misery. The other, to spirit
away and silence anyone who might even remotely suggest the
responsibility of socialism or its rulers — to spirit away
anyone who begins to show signs of thinking for himself. It
is because of the rulers' terror, and their desperate need
to find scapegoats for the failures of socialism, that the
press of a socialist country is always full of stories about
foreign plots and sabotage, and about corruption and
mismanagement on the part of subordinate officials, and why,
periodically, it is necessary to unmask large-scale domestic
plots and to sacrifice major officials and entire factions
in giant purges.
It is because of their terror, and their desperate need to
crush every breath even of potential opposition, that the
rulers of socialism do not dare to allow even purely
cultural activities that are not under the control of the
state. For if people so much as assemble for an art show or
poetry reading that is not controlled by the state, the
rulers must fear the dissemination of dangerous ideas. Any
unauthorized ideas are dangerous ideas, because they can
lead people to begin thinking for themselves and thus to
begin thinking about the nature of socialism and its rulers.
The rulers must fear the spontaneous assembly of a handful
of people in a room, and use the secret police and its
apparatus of spies, informers, and terror either to stop
such meetings or to make sure that their content is entirely
innocuous from the point of view of the state.
Socialism cannot be ruled for very long except by terror. As
soon as the terror is relaxed, resentment and hostility
logically begin to well up against the rulers. The stage is
thus set for a revolution or civil war. In fact, in the
absence of terror, or, more correctly, a sufficient degree
of terror, socialism would be characterized by an endless
series of revolutions and civil wars, as each new group of
rulers proved as incapable of making socialism function
successfully as its predecessors before it. The inescapable
inference to be drawn is that the terror actually
experienced in the socialist countries was not simply the
work of evil men, such as Stalin, but springs from the
nature of the socialist system. Stalin could come to the
fore because his unusual willingness and cunning in the use
of terror were the specific characteristics most required by
a ruler of socialism in order to remain in power. He rose to
the top by a process of socialist natural selection: the
selection of the worst.
I need to anticipate a possible misunderstanding concerning
my thesis that socialism is totalitarian by its nature. This
concerns the allegedly socialist countries run by Social
Democrats, such as Sweden and the other Scandinavian
countries, which are clearly not totalitarian dictatorships.
In such cases, it is necessary to realize that along with
these countries not being totalitarian, they are also not
socialist. Their governing parties may espouse socialism
as their philosophy and their ultimate goal, but socialism
is not what they have implemented as their economic system.
Their actual economic system is that of a hampered market
economy, as Mises termed it. While more hampered than our
own in important respects, their economic system is
essentially similar to our own, in that the characteristic
driving force of production and economic activity is not
government decree but the initiative of private owners
motivated by the prospect of private profit.
The reason that Social Democrats do not establish socialism
when they come to power, is that they are unwilling to do
what would be required. The establishment of socialism as an
economic system requires a massive act of theft — the means
of production must be seized from their owners and turned
over to the state. Such seizure is virtually certain to
provoke substantial resistance on the part of the owners,
resistance which can be overcome only by use of massive
force.
The Communists were and are willing to apply such force, as
evidenced in Soviet Russia. Their character is that of armed
robbers prepared to commit murder if that is what is
necessary to carry out their robbery. The character of the
Social Democrats in contrast is more like that of
pickpockets, who may talk of pulling the big job someday,
but who in fact are unwilling to do the killing that would
be required, and so give up at the slightest sign of serious
resistance.
As for the Nazis, they generally did not have to kill in
order to seize the property of Germans other than Jews. This
was because, as we have seen, they established socialism by
stealth, through price controls, which served to maintain
the outward guise and appearance of private ownership. The
private owners were thus deprived of their property without
knowing it and thus felt no need to defend it by force.
I think I have shown that socialism — actual socialism — is
totalitarian by its very nature.
*****
In the United States at the present time, we do not have
socialism in any form. And we do not have a dictatorship,
let alone a totalitarian dictatorship.
We also do not yet have Fascism, though we are moving
towards it. Among the essential elements that are still
lacking are one-party rule and censorship. We still have
freedom of speech and press and free elections, though both
have been undermined and their continued existence cannot be
guaranteed.
What we have is a hampered market economy that is growing
ever more hampered by ever more government intervention, and
that is characterized by a growing loss of individual
freedom. The growth of the government's economic
intervention is synonymous with a loss of individual freedom
because it means increasingly initiating the use of physical
force to make people do what they do not voluntarily choose
to do or prevent them from doing what they do voluntarily
choose to do.
Since the individual is the best judge of his own interests,
and at least as a rule seeks to do what it is in his
interest to do and to avoid doing what harms his interest,
it follows that the greater the extent of government
intervention, the greater the extent to which individuals
are prevented from doing what benefits them and are instead
compelled to do what causes them loss.
Today, in the United States, government spending, federal,
state, and local, amounts to almost half of the monetary
incomes of the portion of the citizenry that does not work
for the government. Fifteen federal cabinet departments, and
a much larger number of federal regulatory agencies,
together, in most instances with counterparts at the state
and local level, routinely intrude into virtually every area
of the individual citizen's life. In countless ways he is
taxed, compelled, and prohibited.
The effect of such massive government interference is
unemployment, rising prices, falling real wages, a need to
work longer and harder, and growing economic insecurity. The
further effect is growing anger and resentment.
Though the government's policy of interventionism is their
logical target, the anger and resentment people feel are
typically directed at businessmen and the rich instead. This
is a mistake which is fueled for the most part by an
ignorant and envious intellectual establishment and media.
And in conformity with this attitude, since the collapse of
the stock market bubble, which was in fact created by the
Federal Reserve's policy of credit expansion and then
pricked by its temporary abandonment of that policy,
government prosecutors have adopted what appears to be a
particularly vengeful policy toward executives guilty of
financial dishonesty, as though their actions were
responsible for the widespread losses resulting from the
collapse of the bubble. Thus the former head of a major
telecommunications company was recently given a twenty-five
year prison sentence. Other top executives have suffered
similarly.
Even more ominously, the government's power to obtain mere
criminal indictments has become equivalent to the power to
destroy a firm, as occurred in the case of Arthur Andersen,
the major accounting firm. The threatened use of this power
was then sufficient to force major insurance brokerage firms
in the United States to change their managements to the
satisfaction of New York State's Attorney General. There is
no way to describe such developments other than as
conviction and punishment without trial and as extortion by
the government. These are major steps along a very dangerous
path.
Fortunately, there is still sufficient freedom in the United
States to undo all the damage that has been done. There is
first of all the freedom to publicly name it and denounce
it.
More fundamentally, there is the freedom to analyze and
refute the ideas that underlie the destructive policies that
have been adopted or that may be adopted. And that is what
is critical. For the fundamental factor underlying
interventionism and, of course, socialism as well, whether
Nazi or Communist, is nothing but wrong ideas, above all,
wrong ideas about economics and philosophy.
There is now an extensive and growing body of literature
that presents sound ideas in these two vital fields. In my
judgment, the two most important authors of this literature
are Ludwig von Mises and Ayn Rand. An extensive knowledge of
their writings is an indispensable prerequisite for success
in the defense of individual freedom and the free market.
This institute, The Ludwig von Mises Institute, is the
world's leading center for the dissemination of Mises's
ideas. It presents a constant flow of analyses based on his
ideas, analyses that appear in its academic journals, its
books and periodicals, and in its daily website news
articles that deal with the issues of the moment. It
educates college and university students, and young
instructors, in his ideas and the related ideas of other
members of the Austrian school of economics. It does this
through the Mises Summer University, the Austrian Scholars
Conferences, and a variety of seminars.
Two very major ways of fighting for freedom are to educate
oneself to the point of being able to speak and write as
articulately in its defense as do the scholars associated
with this institute or, if one does not have the time or
inclination to pursue such activity, then to financially
support the Institute in its vital work to whatever extent
one can.
It is possible to turn the tide. No single person can
do it. But a large and growing number of intelligent people,
educated in the cause of economic freedom, and speaking up
and arguing in its defense whenever possible, is capable of
gradually forming the attitudes of the culture and thus of
the nature of its political and economic system.
You in this audience are all already involved in this great
effort. I hope you will continue and intensify your
commitment.
* This article was delivered as a lecture at the Mises
Institute's "The Economics of Fascism, Supporters Summit
2005." It is copyright © 2005, by George Reisman.
Permission is hereby granted to reproduce and distribute
it electronically and in print, other than as part of a
book.
(Email notification is requested). All other rights
reserved.
** George Reisman, Ph.D., is Professor of Economics
(Ret.) at Pepperdine University's Graziadio School of
Business and Management in Los Angeles and is the author
of Capitalism: A Treatise on
Economics (Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books,
1996), from which parts of this article were excerpted.
|