| |
DEFENDING
CAPITALISM
AGAINST A CAPITALIST*
By
George Reisman**
|
George Soros, a multibillionaire
stock and commodities speculator, has written an essay titled "The Capitalist
Threat" (The Atlantic Monthly, February 1997). The essential substance of
this essay is the claim that the main contemporary threat to a free society is a fully
free society--i.e., a society of laissez-faire capitalism.
The obviously
self-contradictory nature of this claim may have escaped Soros because he does not use the
term "free society," but the ambiguous expression "open society." Yet
it is clear that insofar as the "open society" is to be considered as something
desirable, it represents a free society, as when Soros writes: "The
Declaration of Independence may be taken as a pretty good approximation of the principles
of an open society...."
Soros presents two lines of argument to try to prove his claim. The first can be
described as epistemological; the second, as economic.
Soros's Epistemological Argument
In his epistemological argument, Soros claims that there is an essential common
denominator between laissez-faire capitalism and communism and Nazism. He writes:
"Although laissez-faire doctrines do not contradict the principles of the open
society the way Marxism-Leninism or Nazi ideas of racial purity did, all these doctrines
have an important feature in common: they all try to justify their claim to ultimate truth
with an appeal to science." Soros has already announced the principle that:
"Since the ultimate truth is beyond the reach of humankind, these ideologies
[ideologies that claim to possess it] have to resort to oppression in order to impose
their vision on society."
Soros appears to understand that "fascism and communism... both relied on the power
of the state to repress the freedom of the individual." Since laissez-faire
capitalism constitutes the absolute freedom of the individual from the state in all areas
of life other than the initiation of physical force, it may, indeed, seem nothing less
than amazing that he places it in the same category as those doctrines. In sharpest
contrast to the present system of massive government intervention, under laissez-faire
capitalism the activities of the state are confined to the protection of the individual
against acts of aggression, such as, for example, murder, robbery, rape, and fraud, and
attack by foreign aggressor governments. The state does not go beyond this strictly
limited function. It does not intrude in people's economic activities; nor does it intrude
in their beliefs, sex lives, or any other aspect of their lives.
Perhaps because he is somewhat embarrassed by the nature of his claim about
laissez-faire capitalism, Soros tries more than once to soften it. In addition to the
modest, nonessential, qualification quoted above, in introducing the alleged important
feature in common," he writes: "I want to emphasize, however, that I am not
putting laissez-faire capitalism in the same category as Nazism or communism. Totalitarian
ideologies deliberately seek to destroy the open society; laissez-faire policies may
endanger it, but only inadvertently." Yet just two sentences later, he declares,
"Nevertheless, because communism and even socialism have been thoroughly discredited,
I consider the threat from the laissez-faire side more potent today than the threat from
totalitarian ideologies." In this sentence, Soros very clearly does once again put
laissez-faire capitalism in the same category as Nazism and communism, however much he may
deny doing so. For the mere discrediting of communism and socialism is not sufficient to
make laissez-faire capitalism into a greater threat than totalitarian ideologies unless
there is something comparably evil about it. To take an analogy from the field of health,
the development of cures or preventives for heart disease and cancer could result in
another life-threatening illness, such as stroke, being elevated to the status of the
major medical threat to human life. But this would be the case only because stroke is
extremely damaging and life threatening in the first place.
As to the alleged evil that laissez-faire capitalism is supposed to share with
communism and Nazism, namely, its claim to "ultimate truth," Soros appears to be
unaware of the fact that communism and Nazism were philosophically incompatible with
claims to truth of any kind, ultimate or otherwise. Both rested on variants of the
doctrine of determinism and denied the universal validity of the laws of logic. According
to Marxism, an individual's ideas were not the result of his consideration of matters of
true or false, but were automatically determined by his membership in an economic class
and reflected the economic interests of that class. Thus, proletarians allegedly had one
set of ideas based on alleged proletarian logic and the alleged class interests of
proletarians, and their class enemies, the bourgeoisie, allegedly had another set of ideas
based on alleged bourgeois logic and the alleged class interests of the bourgeoisie.
According to Nazism, the "interests" and "logics" were along the lines
of racial membership rather than membership in an economic class. Thus, the Nazis held
that the ideas of an Aryan were based on "Aryan logic" and the interests of the
Aryan Race, while the ideas of their enemies, such as the Jews, were based on "Jewish
logic" and the interests of the Jewish Race.
Obviously, the alleged science of Marxism is without any rational basis. Along with,
and underlying, its doctrines of polylogism and class warfare is the labor theory of value
carried to the point of utter absurdity, including the notion that the value of labor
itself is determined by the quantity of labor required to produce it--i.e., by the
quantity of labor required to produce the wage earner's minimum subsistence. It is on this
nonsensical basis that Marxism develops the substance of its claim that profits are based
on the exploitation of labor and that the impoverishment of the masses grows progressively
worse under capitalism.
So too any alleged scientific basis of Nazism is without rational foundation. This is
the case not only because of Nazism's polylogism and doctrine of irreconcilable racial and
national conflicts, and its viewing the human race from the perspective of an animal
breeder, but also because of its socialism (effected through price and wage controls) and
accompanying claims to be able to practice national economic planning, which would require
the direction of the economic system by nothing less than an omniscient deity. (Nazism, it
should never be forgotten stands for Nazional Socialismus.)
Soros seems to be unaware of almost all of the serious, fundamental criticisms to be
made of Marxism and Nazism. In fact, beyond his negative reference to doctrines of racial
purity, the only other thing he says on the subject is, "One of Popper's
accomplishments was to show that a theory like Marxism does not qualify as
science"--as though Popper, rather than von Mises and Böhm-Bawerk had demonstrated
this. (Karl Popper is Soros's main philosophical influence.)
Soros appears almost entirely lacking in familiarity with procapitalist, antisocialist
economic theory and political philosophy subsequent to Adam Smith and David Ricardo. The
closest he comes to displaying any such familiarity is his characterization of F.A. Hayek
as "one of the apostles of laissez-faire," which, unfortunately, is mistaken,
inasmuch as Hayek was an advocate of major aspects of the welfare state, such as social
security. Nowhere does Soros give evidence of having read anything by Ludwig von Mises or
Ayn Rand, by far the two most important advocates of laissez-faire capitalism in the
twentieth century. His lack of knowledge concerning the subject of his essay is made
further evident in his attempt to deny the scientific basis of laissez-faire capitalism,
which he correctly recognizes as economic theory. He writes: "One cannot simply
equate market economics with Marxist economics." But in his very next sentence, he
does so equate it: "Yet laissez-faire ideology, I contend, is just as much a
perversion of supposedly scientific verities as Marxism-Leninism is."
His basis for this outlandish claim is his assumption that what underlies the
laissez-faire ideology is economic theory insofar as it is based on the doctrine of
pure competition and perfect knowledge--a doctrine that the leading advocates of
laissez-faire capitalism not only do not hold, but regard as utterly nonsensical. For
example, a leading conclusion of the doctrine of pure competition is that rivalry is the
opposite of competition. (For a full exposition and critique of this doctrine, see my book
Capitalism, pp. 425-437.)
He also argues the fallaciousness of treating states of equilibrium as really existing,
which, he claims, is essential to economics as a science. He is not aware of the fact that
at least as early as 1940, von Mises demonstrated that economics does not at all depend on
the actual existence of such states--that they are merely tools of thought, helpful in
understanding the way things would develop in the absence of further changes in the basic
data of the market, which changes are in fact incessant.
Closely connected with this, Soros claims that economic theory is invalidated by the
fact that mistakes made in financial markets, which are supposed to discount the future,
can themselves contribute to changing the future. It does not occur to him that economic
theory provides the means of understanding the effects of such mistakes (mistakes which it
shows, incidentally, are the result of government-sponsored credit expansion, when they
are made on a large scale). For example, as the result of such mistakes, the wealth and
income of various investors will be different. The size of various industries may be
different. The result will be some prices that are higher and other prices that are lower,
depending on whether the effect of the mistakes has been to increase the demand or
decrease the supply of the good in question, or to decrease the demand or increase the
supply of the good in question. In essence, Soros attempts to dispose of the scientific
basis of laissez-faire capitalism by breaking down open doors and refuting strawmen.
Like the words "open society," the words "ultimate truth" are
ambiguous. They are used by Soros as a pejorative that embraces both knowledge that is
held with certainty, because it is based on fact and logic, and assertions that are
arbitrarily but forcefully declared to be true without evidence or in contradiction of the
evidence. It is only in this way that Soros can bring under one epistemological umbrella
the scientifically supported doctrine of laissez-faire capitalism and the irrationalist
doctrines of Nazism and communism. He does so, simply by using the words "ultimate
truth" as a description of the claims of all three doctrines.
Soros appears to believe that rational certainty is simply impossible. This is implicit
in his view that the essential element of the "open society" is recognition of
human fallibility: "I envisage the open society as a society open to improvement. We
start with the recognition of our own fallibility.... instead of claiming that those
principles [the principles proclaimed in the Declaration of Independence] are
self-evident, we ought to say that they are consistent with our fallibility... Could the
recognition of our imperfect understanding serve to establish the open society as a
desirable form of social organization? ... We must promote a belief in our own fallibility
to the status that we normally confer on a belief in ultimate truth."
At one point, Soros even goes so far as to say: "Why does nobody have access to
the ultimate truth? The answer became clear: We live in the same universe that we are
trying to understand, and our perceptions can influence the events in which we
participate. If our thoughts belonged to one universe and their subject matter to another,
the truth might be within our grasp: we could formulate statements corresponding to the
facts, and the facts would serve as reliable criteria for deciding whether the statements
were true."
This statement, which suggests an element of Platonism, appears to imply that we are in
a better position to acquire knowledge concerning conditions in a remote galaxy than we
are to acquire knowledge concerning conditions here on earth.
In the very next paragraph, Soros claims that "There is a realm where these
conditions [i.e., two universes, one for the observer, the other for the observed]
prevail: natural science. But. . . in social and political affairs the participants'
perceptions help to determine reality. In these situations facts do not necessarily
constitute reliable criteria for judging the truth of statements." Later, he seems to
argue that the so-called social sciences, such as economics, are chronically in the same
position as physics in the realm of quantum mechanics, where the Heisenberg uncertainty
principle is operative. He declares: "The theories of social science relate to their
subject matter in a reflexive manner. That is to say, they can influence events in a way
that the theories of natural science cannot. Heisenberg's famous uncertainty principle
implies that the act of observation may interfere with the behavior of quantum particles;
but it is the observation that creates the effect, not the uncertainty principle itself.
In the social sphere, theories have the capacity to alter the subject matter to which they
relate."
The truth here is that economics and every other subject whose ideas influence the
world in which man lives, such as, above all, philosophy, are no different in their most
basic epistemology than physics and the other natural sciences. Economics and philosophy
are in a position to understand the effects of human actions on reality and to distinguish
between the different effects of different human actions operating as causes. That is to
say, they are able to distinguish between the world as man has made it up to now, and the
world that man could make in the future if he were guided by different ideas that produced
different effects.
Sound economics, for example, distinguishes between the effects of wrong ideas, such as
those which result in economic stagnation, mass unemployment, inflation, price controls,
and socialism, and the effects of right ideas, such as those which result in the existence
of economic progress, free labor and product markets, sound money, and private ownership
of the means of production, all of which preclude the effects of the corresponding wrong
ideas. It is simply absurd to argue that the fact that man's own ideas and actions change
the world prevents him in any way from understanding the world. He observes differences in
his external conditions and differences in his beliefs and logically connects them on the
basis of principles derived from a combination of experience and introspection, such as,
in economics, the principle that other things being equal, individuals prefer to earn a
higher income rather than a lower income and to pay lower prices rather than higher
prices.
In physics and natural science in general, the only way that knowledge can be gained is
precisely on the basis of man's interaction with the world, ranging from a baby's banging
his spoon on the counter of his high chair to the most complex controlled laboratory
experiment. Man always learns by discovering connections between his actions and their
effects on the external world and by a process of generalizing from the particular to the
universal.
Man's physical actions in the world do not change physical laws, nor do his economic
actions change economic laws. For example, a price control that obliges suppliers to
provide a good without profit or with a less-than-competitive rate of profit, is a
comparable affront to natural law as a legislative demand that the producers make the good
out of physically impossible materials, such as produce gasoline out of sand instead of
crude oil or construct buildings out of air and water instead of steel and concrete.
Economic law shows that the good will not continue to be voluntarily supplied under such a
price control, just as physical law shows that it cannot physically be produced from such
materials.
Contrary to Soros, it is precisely man's ability to be rationally certain that is
essential to the freedom of the individual. The reliability of reason underlies the value
of reason and, in so doing, it underlies the distinctive value of Man, whose fundamental
distinguishing characteristic is, of course, his possession of reason. And since reason is
possessed by the individual human being, the reliability of reason is what establishes
both the value and the competence of the individual human being. The value and competence
of the individual is the foundation of his possession of individual rights. It is
symbolized by the rattlesnake flag of the American Revolution, with its warning to
arbitrary government: "Don't Tread on Me"--because, as a rational being I am a
being of the highest value and competence and a force to be reckoned with when my rights
are violated. The principle that the government must respect the rights of the individual
is, of course, what underlies the individual's freedom from the government.
The fact that reason enables Man to know truth reliably--with certainty--is what
establishes freedom as the ally of reason. Because reason gives Man the power to
understand truth, truth needs no support from the use of physical force. It has the power
of reason on its side. As a leading historical example, Galileo did not need the use of
force to establish the truth that the Earth revolves around the Sun. He established it by
means of fact and logic. But those who wished to go on maintaining that the Sun revolves
around the Earth, did need the use of physical force, because they had no other means of
upholding their proposition. The rational certainty of the advocates of laissez-faire
capitalism in the truth of their cause only serves to reinforce their dedication to
respecting the rights and freedom of the individual that is demanded by the very nature of
their ideas and program.
So much for Soros's epistemological argument against laissez-faire capitalism.
|
The "Open Society" Versus the
Free Society
Before I turn to his economic arguments, I want to point out that the use Soros makes
of the concepts of "fallibility" and "ultimate truth" are instances of
an epistemological fallacy. That is, both of these concepts are secondary, derivative
concepts. They both presuppose the more fundamental concept of truth--truth that is known
as truth, with certainty. They would not be possible without the underlying concept of
truth. Yet, at the same time, they are used by Soros to deny and negate the concept of
truth.
No one would be able to recognize an instance of fallibility, that is, an instance in
which he had mistakenly believed he was right but in fact was wrong, if he could not know
the truth and distinguish it from error. For example, I can incorrectly add a column of
figures without realizing it. In this instance I have been fallible. But the only way I
can possibly identify my error is that I am able to add the column of figures correctly.
Only by establishing and recognizing the correct answer, can I recognize that my previous
answer was wrong. If I could not establish and recognize the correct answer, I could never
know when I was wrong. There would be no standard of what constituted error, if not for
the existence of truth and Man's ability to recognize it with certainty.
Soros's concept of "the open society" is another instance of the same
fallacy. By means of its use, he not only commits the contradiction I described earlier of
claiming that the main threat to a free society is a fully free society, but he seeks to
negate the existence of all freedom. He writes that in the open society, "People must
be free to think and act, subject only to limits imposed by the common interests. Where
the limits are must also be determined by trial and error." (Italics mine.) Thus,
he openly argues that the freedom of the individual is to be abridged out of deference to
unspecified common interests, whose nature, according to him cannot even be reliably
known, and that the limits to the abridgment of freedom are to be set by trial and error.
The standard Soros offers for judging the process of trial and error is this:
"Unfortunately, in human affairs the facts do not provide reliable criteria of truth,
yet we need some generally agreed-upon standards by which the process of trial and error
can be judged. All cultures and religions offer such standards; the open society cannot do
without them. The innovation in an open society is that whereas most cultures and
religions regard their own values as absolute, an open society, which is aware of many
cultures and religions, must regard its own shared values as a matter of debate and
choice. To make the debate possible, there must be general agreement on at least one
point: that the open society is a desirable form of social organization."
It follows from this statement that unless our standard for judging the process of
trial and error is to be that "the open society is a desirable form of social
organization," which provides no standard at all, all we are left with as providing
such a standard is "cultures and religions," whose various standards and shared
values are to be "a matter of debate and choice," to be decided by no known
principle. What all this means is that in Soros's vision of the "open society,"
the freedom of the individual can be violated for any reason, if enough people can be
found willing to claim that their unprovable, undefined, subjective common interests
require it.
Ironically, Soros seems prepared to apply the same collectivist moral-political
principle for abridging the freedom of the individual as the Nazis. The Nazis' principle
was: "Gemeinnutz geht vor Eigennutz (The common interest comes before
self-interest)." Soros's virtually identical principle is contained in the words:
"Unless it is tempered by the recognition of a common interest that ought to take
precedence over particular interests, our present system--which, however imperfect,
qualifies as an open society--is liable to break down."
Soros's Economic Arguments
I turn now to the various economic arguments Soros puts forward against laissez-faire
capitalism. Apart from those I have already considered in the course of dealing with his
epistemological argument, namely those concerning "perfect competition," the
absence of equilibrium, and the mistakes made in financial markets, there are four others
that I can discern. These concern the alleged conflict between economic competition and
social cooperation, the alleged need for the redistribution of wealth because of the
existence of economic inequality, advertising and the alleged corruption of values by
money, and financial crises.
Competition
The argument concerning competition is simply the entirely unsupported assertion that
"Too much competition and too little cooperation can cause intolerable inequities and
instability." This statement, indeed, is the immediate basis, prior to his use of the
epistemological argument, that Soros gives for extending the threat to the "open
society" from fascism and communism to include laissez-faire capitalism. It is
introduced with the sentence, "I contend that an open society may also be threatened
from the opposite direction--from excessive individualism."
Soros appears to think that the truth of his statement about competition and
cooperation is self-evident. This is because, like the immense majority of contemporary
intellectuals, he takes for granted that the nature of economic competition is essentially
the same as that of competition in the animal kingdom, namely, the law of the jungle and
survival of the fittest. In fact, in his later discussion of redistribution, he writes:
"The laissez-faire argument against income redistribution invokes the doctrine of the
survival of the fittest." His utter confusion on this subject is shown by the fact
that in the very next sentence he appears positively to endorse the concept of survival of
the fittest. He writes: "The argument [for survival of the fittest] is undercut by
the fact that wealth is passed on by inheritance, and the second generation is rarely as
fit as the first." The implication, of course, is that what is wrong with the
principle of survival of the fittest is that it cannot be practiced sufficiently, because
the heirs are not fit enough.
In the sentence after this one, however, Soros once again reverses field and declares:
"In any case, there is something wrong with making the survival of the fittest a
guiding principle of civilized society."
The truth is that economic competition is the very opposite of competition in
the animal kingdom. First of all, it is not a competition in the grabbing off of scarce
nature-given supplies, as it is in the animal kingdom. Rather, it is a competition in the
positive creation of new and additional wealth. Unlike the lions in the jungle, who
must compete for a limited supply of nature-given necessities, such as zebras and other
game animals, which they have no power to enlarge, competition among business firms is
competition in the creation of new and improved products and more efficient methods of
production. For example, General Motors and Toyota do not at all compete in the grabbing
off of a limited supply of nature-given automobiles from automobile herds or automobile
trees. On the contrary, they compete in the development of newer, better automobiles
produced by progressively more efficient methods of production. Their action, and the
action of business firms in general, thus serves to enlarge the supply of products.
As the result of its basic nature, so far from being a process of survival of the
fittest, economic competition is the foundation of the survival of practically
everyone, including those who from a purely biological point of view are not at all
very "fit." Just think of the effect of competition among pharmaceutical
manufacturers, the makers of eye glasses and hearing aids, and so forth, on the sick and
on people who suffer from poor eyesight or poor hearing. Think of the effect of
competition among farmers and farm equipment manufacturers on the hungry. Think of the
effect of the competition among of all kinds of machinery makers on the condition of all
those people who would otherwise be fatigued and exhausted.
Furthermore, as Ricardo and von Mises have shown, because of the law of comparative
advantage there is room for all in the competition of a capitalist society,
including those whose productive abilities are modest in every respect. There is room for
such people provided only that they concentrate on those areas in which the degree of
their lesser capability is least, leaving the more capable people to concentrate on those
areas in which the degree of their greater capability is greatest.
For example, we may assume that Bill Gates, in addition to his outstanding capability in
leading and developing a major industry, is so gifted that he would be capable of doing
almost any job more efficiently than anyone else could do it. Even so, Gates does not
attempt even remotely to do all such jobs. Rather he concentrates on the one job in which
his productive superiority is greatest. Although he might do the work of his vice
presidents better and more efficiently than they, not to mention the work of his secretary
and even that of the janitors at Microsoft, he does not do any of these jobs. It pays him
to leave such jobs to others, because it frees his time to concentrate on his area of
greatest advantage, which is running Microsoft.
Indeed, Gates is actually outcompeted by these less capable people for the jobs that
they succeed in doing. He is outcompeted even by his janitors--for the job of janitor. For
example, the fact that he might be able to sweep a floor in half the time of any of his
janitors, counts as nothing alongside the fact that running Microsoft enables him to earn
an income that is many thousands of times greater than that of a janitor. In effect, a
janitor is capable of accomplishing half the work in a given period of time, but at a cost
that is thousands of times less than what Gates would have to ask in order to earn as much
as he does in running Microsoft. Even though it takes the janitor twice as long to do the
same job as it would take Gates to do it, he does it for vastly less money, and thus
easily outcompetes Gates, and everyone else between himself and Gates, for the job of
janitor.
Going still further, because Gates and numerous other productive geniuses are able to
concentrate on the continuous improvement of production, it becomes possible for the
janitors of the world to own such things as computers and automobiles, and practically all
the other goods that make up a modern standard of living, including, of course, a growing
abundance of food, clothing, and housing.
As von Mises showed, economic competition, so far from being in conflict with
social cooperation, is precisely the mechanism that organizes the system of social
cooperation. It organizes the social division of labor, which is the essence and core
of social cooperation, by selecting the right individuals for the right jobs, in
accordance with the principle of comparative advantage. At the same time, it determines to
what extent which products will serve which markets, and to what extent which methods of
production are used in the production of the various products. The only element of
"survival of the fittest" that is present is survival of the best products
and best methods of production, for the sake of the survival and well-being of all
human beings.
Whoever claims that economic competition represents "survival of the fittest"
in the sense of the law of the jungle, provides the clearest possible evidence of his lack
of knowledge of economic science.
|
Economic Inequality and the
Redistribution of Wealth
Such lack of knowledge, unfortunately, is equally manifest in Soros's views on economic
inequality and the allegedly resulting need for the redistribution of wealth. On this
subject, he writes: "Wealth does accumulate in the hands of its owners, and if there
is no mechanism for redistribution, the inequities can become intolerable. `Money is like
muck, not good except it be spread.' Francis Bacon was a profound economist."
Whoever holds such views is unaware of the fact that in a division-of-labor, capitalist
society, privately owned wealth in the form of capital, works to the benefit of all--the
nonowners as well as the owners. For example, the physical beneficiaries of the automobile
factories are not the owners of those factories but the buyers of the cars. Indeed, this
principle applies to all privately owned means of production that serve the market--e.g.,
to stores and warehouses, farms and mines, as well as to factories. The physical
beneficiaries are the buyers of the products, who need not own so much as a single share
of stock in the firms that produce the goods they buy. Indeed, the extent to which
consumers' goods are purchased by the owners and creditors of business firms, such as
stockholders and bondholders, out of profits, interest, and dividends, is quite small
relative to the proportion that is purchased out of wages and salaries--on the order of
about ten percent of total consumption.
Closely related to this benefit to the buyers of the products is the benefit of
privately owned capital to the sellers of labor. The capital of the automobile companies,
and of all other business firms, is the foundation of the demand for labor. The greater is
that capital, the greater is the demand for labor and thus wage rates. Thus there is a
twofold benefit that nonowners of the means of production obtain from the capital owned by
others: namely, such capital is the source both of the supply of the products that they
buy and of the demand for the labor that they sell.
Soros and the other redistributors are apparently thinking of privately owned means of
production as though they were consumers' goods or as though they existed outside of the
context of a division-of-labor society. Only if all wealth were of the character of such
consumers' goods as a giant bowl of spaghetti, say, or if the means of production were not
used to produce for the market, but only for the personal consumption of their owners and
their families, would wealth be of no use to others "except as it be spread." In
the context of a division-of-labor, capitalist society the overwhelmingly greater part of
the wealth of the capitalists is in the form of means of production that serve the market.
Redistributing such wealth would only serve to cause the consumption of capital and to
prevent its further accumulation. These results would be profoundly against the interests
of everyone, including the great mass of nonowners of the means of production.
For practical purposes, I can view myself as a nonowner of means of production, in that
practically all of my consumption is supported out of a salary that I earn, rather than
out of profits, dividends, or interest. Despite my being a nonowner of the means of
production I would lose very substantially if, for example, the government were to attempt
to make me an owner of the means of production by nationalizing them and declaring every
citizen thereafter to be an equal owner. Even apart from the utter economic chaos that
would result from the loss of the price system that would be entailed, the effect would be
that instead of having the benefit of profit-and-loss incentives and the freedoms of
competition and individual initiative operating on my behalf in the activities of my
suppliers, I would henceforth have only disinterested government monopolists and
bureaucrats as my suppliers.
I would also lose if the government were to increase the taxes it levies on business
firms--or on wealthy individuals who heavily save and invest in business firms--and
distribute the proceeds to the average citizen. If, for example, the government were to
raise taxes on corporate profits, or on personal incomes that would otherwise be heavily
saved and invested, by, say, $100 billion a year and then distribute $1,000 a year to me
and to each of 99,999,999 other nonowners of the means of production, I would lose
substantially. True enough, I would gain something from the $1,000 I personally received.
But I would gain virtually nothing from the $1,000 received by each of all of the other
nonowners of the means of production--i.e., from the $99,999,999,000 that they
collectively received. For they, like me, would almost certainly consume practically all
of what they received. At the same time, I would lose greatly by the withdrawal of $100
billion from the production of the goods I buy and from the support of the demand for the
labor I sell.
The withdrawal of these funds would reduce the demand both for labor and for capital
goods. In reducing the demand for labor, it would cause wage rates to be less or
unemployment to be greater. In reducing the demand for capital goods, while the
expenditure of the recipients of the money raised the demand for consumers' goods, it
would cause the demand for capital goods relative to the demand for consumers' goods to
fall and thus reduce the production of capital goods relative to that of consumers' goods.
This would reduce the rate at which the economic system would be able to accumulate
capital goods. The further result would be a reduction in the rate at which the
productivity of labor and thus real wages could be increased, for these vitally depend on
the supply of capital goods per worker. These results would be reinforced by the reduction
in the incentives to improve production that such taxation entails. If carried far enough,
the process of redistribution results in economic stagnation and economic retrogression.
It is tantamount to eating the seed corn.
So much for Soros's argument for the need for redistribution to address the allegedly
intolerable situation of rich owners of means of production having too much wealth
invested in the production of goods that are sold overwhelmingly to nonowners of the means
of production and in supporting the demand for the labor that the nonowners of the means
of production sell.
Advertising and the Alleged Corruption of
Values by Money
Soros declares that "Advertising, marketing, even packaging, aim at shaping
people's preferences rather than, as laissez-faire theory holds, merely responding to
them. Unsure of what they stand for, people increasingly rely on money as the criterion of
value. What is more expensive is considered better. The value of a work of art can be
judged by the price it fetches. People deserve respect and admiration because they are
rich. What used to be a medium of exchange has usurped the place of fundamental values,
reversing the relationship postulated by economic theory."
Soros's statement about advertising, however widely accepted it may be, is
fundamentally mistaken. True enough, the advertiser wants to induce people to buy the
advertised product. But successful advertising usually requires that when the customer
does buy the product, the product is such that the customer will like it, will buy it
again, and will recommend it to others. Advertising of such products is almost certain to
be economically worthwhile. On the other hand, advertising products that people do not
like after they buy them, which they won't buy again, and which they will tell others not
to buy, is almost certain to be an economic failure. In other words, the key to successful
advertising is to be able to offer and advertise products that effectively meet the
customer's actual needs and wants.
Soros is certainly right about many people being unsure of what they stand for. How
could they be sure of anything in the face of a constant cultural drumbeat that proclaims
precisely Soros's own apparent leading principle of fallibility and thus of self-doubt?
Nevertheless, however true this may be today in connection with matters such as
philosophical and moral principles, it is still the case that in the area of personal
material satisfactions, people almost always know very well what it is that they like and
what it is that they do not like. No amount of advertising on behalf of the culinary
virtues of steamed vegetables could succeed in making very many people prefer their taste
to that of chocolate bars or ice cream. No amount of advertising on behalf of candles and
lanterns could succeed in inducing many people to give up the use of electric light. No
amount of advertising on behalf of horses or bicycles could succeed in convincing many
people to give up their automobiles.
Understandably, people do and should attach an important measure of respect and
admiration to those who are rich. To the extent that people become rich by means of
production and exchange, they accomplish genuine good on a large scale, good both for
themselves and for those with whom they deal. To be sure, there can be cases in which
esteem for financial success may be carried to excess and lead one to overlook otherwise
glaring deficiencies. The great wealth of Mr. Soros, for example, may lead people to apply
a more lenient standard than usual to the opinions he expresses about matters such as
economic theory and political philosophy.
|
Financial Crises
Soros writes: "History has shown that financial markets do break down, causing
economic depression and social unrest. The breakdowns have led to the evolution of central
banking and other forms of regulation. Laissez-faire ideologues like to argue that the
breakdowns were caused by faulty regulations, not by unstable markets. There is some
validity in their argument, because if our understanding is inherently imperfect,
regulations are bound to be defective. But their argument rings hollow, because it fails
to explain why the regulations were imposed in the first place. It sidesteps the issue by
using a different argument, which goes like this: since regulations are faulty,
unregulated markets are perfect."
In this passage, Soros argues that depressions and mass unemployment are the result of
laissez-faire capitalism and that it is in response to this fact that government
intervention in money and banking has taken place. He appears to believe that originally
there was laissez-faire capitalism, but, nevertheless, depressions occurred, which
necessitated government intervention. The same alleged sequence of events is present in
many of the arguments commonly made against capitalism: For example, there is poverty;
thus the government must intervene. People cannot afford their rent; the government must
impose rent controls. Wages are low and hours are long; the government must enact labor
and social legislation and encourage labor unions. And so on and on. Strangely, it does
not seem to occur to Soros, who has stressed the influence of people's ideas on the social
reality in which they live, that the actual basis of government intervention is never the
facts themselves but always the ideas that people hold about the causes of their
problems and their belief that the government has the ability to solve them.
The fundamental reason that the advocates of laissez-faire capitalism oppose government
intervention in money and banking, and everywhere else, is their basic conviction that the
individual's pursuit of his material self-interest under freedom is the one and only way
that people can actually achieve their self-interests. Each individual is motivated to
achieve his self-interest, and, if he thinks about the means, can actually succeed in
doing so, provided that he is free to do so, that is, is free of the initiation of
physical force by others, including, above all, by the government. At the same time,
precisely because freedom means the absence of the initiation of physical force, the
pursuit of self-interest by any individual means that insofar as he is to obtain the
cooperation of others, whether as workers or suppliers, or as customers, he must
simultaneously serve their self-interests. For he too is precluded from using force, and
thus can obtain their cooperation only by voluntary means, which requires that he make
their cooperation with him beneficial to them, indeed, more beneficial than any
alternative they may have available for the sale of their labor or goods or for the
expenditure of their money.
The violation of freedom, on the other hand, prevents the individual from accomplishing
the good he would otherwise have accomplished both for himself and for others. The result
is that to the extent that freedom is violated, the achievement of good is prevented. It
is precisely for these reasons that the freest societies are the most prosperous ones, and
that unfree societies are, or are in process of becoming, poor societies.
Consistent with the above foundation of basic principle, the advocates of laissez-faire
capitalism argue that depressions are not the result of anything inherent in the economic
system. They are the result of credit expansion, that is, the manufacture of new and
additional money out of thin air and its injection into the market in the form of new and
additional loans. This process leads businessmen to become financially illiquid, as they
come to substitute the prospect of borrowing easily and profitably for the holding of
actual cash balances, and as they further run down cash balances in the conviction that
rising sales revenues, generated by the new and additional money, will enable them easily
and profitably to turn inventories into cash as and when they made need it. Whenever the
process of credit expansion comes to an end, substantially slows, or, indeed, fails to
accelerate as rapidly as the market may have assumed it would, a "credit crunch"
and liquidity crisis break out. This constitutes the onset of the depression. In the
depression, banks that have created substantial quantities of new and additional money in
the granting of loans, find that the value of those loans becomes less than the money that
they have created. When their customers find out, bank runs begin and much of such money
is simply wiped out.
Historically, credit expansion is a practice that originated with private banks that
accepted money in exchange either for paper banknotes that they issued or for checking
deposits that they created. To the extent that the banks then used the money thus turned
over to them, to lend out, or to support the issuance of further banknotes or the creation
of further checking deposits which were loaned out, they engaged in a process of money
creation and credit expansion. For the bank notes and checking deposits that they had
issued in exchange for that money, could be spent as the full equivalent of that money. As
a result, making it possible to spend both the equivalent of that money and the money
itself, or the original equivalent plus still further equivalents, represented an
increase in the quantity of money.
Advocates of laissez-faire capitalism hold that credit expansion would long ago have
been reduced to insignificance if not protected and fostered by a centuries-old policy of
government intervention in money and banking. This intervention has included such measures
as restrictions on competition among banks, thereby preventing the growth of better
managed, more conservative banks; allowing insolvent banks to suspend payments, thereby
enabling them to escape the consequences of their actions and thus perpetuating and
encouraging the practice of credit expansion; using periodic bank examinations to create
the illusion of financial soundness on the part of banks practicing credit expansion, thus
promoting public confidence in such banks and thereby enabling them to remain in
existence. More recently, government intervention has taken the form of the provision of
deposit insurance, and, above all, the establishment of central banking and the use of the
central bank again and again to maintain and promote credit expansion through the
provision of additional monetary reserves to the banks. Indeed, the promotion of credit
expansion has been a leading policy of almost all governments ever since they learned of
the practice.
Thus government intervention is what has been responsible for the perpetuation of
financial crises and for the continuing potential of such crises to occur in the future.
To the extent that the recurrence of major financial crises has been avoided in the
present era, it has been at the price of continuous inflation of the money supply, which
has been made possible only by placing the government in a position in which it stands
outside the economic system and above the citizenry, with the power to create its own
money. This situation is what has led to the delusion that the government financially
supports the people and is capable both of showering free benefits upon them and, at the
same time, making them all prosperous by means of increasing the amount of money that
everyone can earn.
The problem of financial crises confirms the fact that what is necessary is precisely laissez-faire
capitalism, not any form of "mixed economy." Attempting to address the problem
of financial crises through government intervention is what has led to the government's
having the awesome powers, monetary, financial, and otherwise, that it presently
possesses. The government's ability to create money out of thin air and to support an
inflationist banking system, is what has led to the tremendous growth in its size and
power. For this is what has allowed the government to appear in the guise of Santa Claus.
Laissez Faire and the Future
Soros describes the power and influence of the laissez-faire ideology in a way that, at
first at least, seems extremely puzzling. He depicts it as a presently existing, major
cultural force. For example, he writes, "Insofar as there is a dominant belief in our
society today, it is a belief in the magic of the marketplace. The doctrine of
laissez-faire capitalism holds that the common good is best served by the uninhibited
pursuit of self-interest."
The truth, of course, is that few ideas have less influence in today's society than
that of laissez-faire capitalism. Its lack of influence is obvious when one considers such
leading facts as these: There are currently over 19 million government employees in the
United States, enforcing over forty thousand pages of federal regulations, tens of
thousand of pages of state and local government regulations, and countless volumes of
federal, state, and local statutes, with the number of laws and regulations growing by
thousands of pages annually. Recent [1997] data show that total government spending in the United
States, including transfer payments under programs such as social security and medicare,
amounts to $2.5 trillion out of total incomes of $6.2 trillion, i.e., about 40 percent. A
successful individual is subject, directly and indirectly, to combined federal and state
corporate and personal income taxes at a total, cumulative rate of approximately 70
percent. On top of all this, the extent of the fall in the long-term future purchasing
power of all contracts denominated in a fixed number of dollars, and thus of the possible
future impoverishment of tens of millions of citizens, is anybody's guess, given the
government's power to increase the quantity of money without any fixed, externally imposed
limit. Such facts, of course, stand in the most forceful, direct contradiction of any
actually existing, present influence of the laissez-faire ideology.
The only way that I can understand Soros's belief in the influence of the laissez-faire
ideology is by assuming that he is focused on its potential future influence much more
than on its present, actual influence. This would be consistent with his record of success
as a speculator. An essential requirement of such success is becoming aware sooner than
almost anyone else of essential facts indicating the course of future events. I believe
that the essential facts that he is concerned with in this instance are not only that
"communism and even socialism have been thoroughly discredited," but also that,
as a result, laissez-faire capitalism is now the logical alternative and is thus the
wave of the future. The prospect frightens him, and his article is an effort to
prevent it from coming to pass, by means of finding another alternative.
What Soros has realized, I believe, is that, given the profound failure of socialism,
caused by its fatally flawed nature, and the growing recognition that the problems
experienced in basically capitalistic societies are the result of the socialistic elements
that have been grafted onto them, people should now, in all reason, be turning to the
consideration of laissez-faire capitalism. For it is the logically consistent opposite of
the system they know to have failed, and the logically consistent positive application of
the system they now know to have been successful--capitalism.
Contrary to Soros's intention, the inference that
laissez-faire capitalism is the wave of the future is significantly reinforced by his
essay and by the favorable reception it has received among the enemies of laissez-faire
capitalism.
This is because what his essay and its favorable
reception reveal is that the opponents of laissez-faire capitalism have nothing of
substance to say in support of their opposition. I have certainly proved this in the case
of Soros's essay itself. It is seriously confused and devoid of effective argument. That
despite this, it is popular, implies that the admirers of Soros's essay have no
more knowledge concerning the actual nature of laissez-faire capitalism than he does. They
know so little, that they believe his arguments actually have merit. In addition, they
take the fact that Soros is a highly successful capitalist to mean that he speaks with the
authority of one who knows the system from the inside, so to speak. Thus, if his appraisal
of laissez-faire capitalism agrees with their appraisal, then, they believe, they must
surely be right in their appraisal, for he must surely know what is wrong with
laissez-faire capitalism. Unfortunately for them, he doesn't know.
What all this implies is that when and if a sufficient number of intelligent people
choose to gain actual knowledge of laissez-faire capitalism, there will be nothing to
resist its advance--certainly not the arguments of Mr. Soros and those who believe in
them.
Choosing to gain knowledge is, of course, a very big "if." People, even the
most intelligent people, can choose not to think and not to make the effort required to
gain knowledge. Indeed, such a negative choice is encouraged by the epistemological
doctrine that Mr. Soros champions, namely, that our primary intellectual attribute is that
we are fallible and thus incapable of ever arriving at reliable knowledge in the first
place.
Nevertheless, if even Mr. Soros, and those who agree with his essay, were to make a
serious effort to learn about laissez-faire capitalism, by reading and studying the books
of its leading advocates, they might find that they should welcome rather than fear its
establishment, and that they should join in the work of helping to establish a society of
laissez-faire capitalism.
Click here to see Atlantic
Monthly's letter of rejection of this essay.
Happily, Atlantic Monthly's default has
proven to be an opportunity for The Free Radical,
a publication of unusual courage and intellect, edited by Lindsay Perigo. The first half
of the essay appears in Issue Number 27, October/November 1997. The second half will
appear in The Free Radical's next issue.
*Copyright
© 1997 by George Reisman. All rights reserved.
**George
Reisman, Ph.D., is professor of Economics at Pepperdine University’s
Graziadio School of Business and Management and is the author of
Capitalism: A Treatise
on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books,
1996).
Return to Top of
Page
|
|
|