Monday, August 28, 2006
Incitement to Class War
at The New York Times/Pravda
The lead article in today’s
New York
Times/Pravda is titled
”Real Wages Fail
to Match a Rise in Productivity.”
The piece is a denunciation of capitalism and its
offshoot “globalization” for allowing such a thing
to happen. In the print edition of the newspaper,
the subhead ominously declares, “POLITICAL FALLOUT
IS SEEN.”
As the means of providing a thinly veiled statement
of the doctrine of class warfare, the article quotes
the publisher of “a nonpartisan political
newsletter”:
“There are two economies out there,” Mr. Cook, the
political analyst, said. “One has been just white
hot, going great guns. Those are the people who have
benefited from globalization, technology, greater
productivity and higher corporate earnings.
“And then there’s the working stiffs,’’ he added,
“who just don’t feel like they’re getting ahead
despite the fact that they’re working very hard. And
there are a lot more people in that group than the
other group.”
The main “expert” cited in the article is an
economic illiterate employed by the Economic Policy
Institute, a leftist “research group.” He opines,
“`If I had to sum it up,’ . . . `it comes down to
bargaining power and the lack of ability of many in
the work force to claim their fair share of
growth.’” Apparently, this “expert” believes, as
does the Times
and the left in general, that the
relationship between profits and wages is determined
by some form of “bargaining” and that whatever goes
to profits is at the expense of what goes to wages
and wage earners.
The fact, of course, is that the number of workers
employers seek to employ is determined by the wage
rates that they must pay, and is the larger, the
lower are wage rates, and the smaller, the higher
are wage rates. (This relationship goes under the
name “demand” and is typically illustrated by means
of a downward sloping line called a “demand curve.”
The Times and its “experts” should attempt to make themselves
familiar with the concept.) In a free market, wage
rates must simultaneously be low enough on the
demand curve for labor, to make possible the
employment of all those able and willing to work and
high enough to limit the amount of labor sought by
employers to the supply of labor available.
Attempts to force wage rates higher, through
“bargaining,” i.e., the coercive “collective
bargaining” of monopoly labor unions serve only to
cause unemployment, by reducing the quantity of
labor demanded below the supply available.
Often, the unemployment caused in this way in a
given line of work, can be offset by expanded
employment in other lines of work. For example,
skilled electricians and carpenters who are
prevented from working as electricians or carpenters
because of the artificially high wages imposed by
their respective unions, may very well end up being
employed in other, lesser lines of work. But when
they are, wage rates in those lesser lines have had
to fall, in order to absorb the increase in the
supply of labor resulting from the reduction in jobs
offered in the unionized lines. Or, if these lines
are unionized too, or if their wage rates simply
follow union scales, and so cannot fall when the
available supply of labor increases, then the
employment of the displaced electricians and
carpenters shifts the unemployment to other workers.
In sum, the formula of the
Times
and the rest of the economically ignorant left for
raising wages relative to profits is to cause either
unemployment or arbitrary inequalities in wage rates
among different occupations. In both cases, the
further result is less production, higher prices,
and a lower standard of living.
This is not the place to address the numerous
further fallacies that center on the belief that
what goes to businessmen and capitalists as profits
in a free economy is at the expense of what goes to
wage earners as wages. Those fallacies must be the
subject of future articles.
I remind readers that what actually does help to
explain the rise in profits at the expense of wages
in today’s highly interventionist economy is
environmental
legislation. In essence, this has served
to create an artificial scarcity of land and natural
resources relative to labor and to elevate the
income derived from their ownership—income which the
classical economists called land rent—relative to
wages. Land rent, of course, appears in the economic
statistics as profit. (For further details, please
see my July 24 article
”How
Environmentalism Raises Profits at the Expense of
Wages.”)
Government budget deficits are also a factor. Such
deficits represent government spending that is
financed with funds raised at the expense of private
capital spending, which spending includes both wage
payments and expenditures for capital goods. The
effect of the deficits is not only that wage
payments in the economic system are smaller, but
also that profits in the economic system are
artificially increased. This last occurs because
while business sales revenues in the economic system
remain the same, with government spending taking the
place of private spending, the costs that business
firms deduct from their sales revenues end up being
less than they otherwise would have been. Costs are
less because the expenditure that gives rise to
costs—i.e., precisely the spending for labor and
capital goods by business—is less. The deficits take
funds away from business spending and thus later on
from the costs that reflect prior business spending.
In this way, their effect is to make profits higher
as well as making wages lower.
Whoever wants to raise the wages of the average
worker should not be advocating monopoly labor
unionism and the unemployment and higher prices that
it causes, but the repeal of environmental
legislation, which raises land rents at the expense
of wages. And, of course, in addition, he should be
advocating the end of government budget deficits and
the repeal of all other legislation that stands in
the way of saving and capital accumulation or
otherwise undermines the productivity of labor.
Saving and capital accumulation both raise the
demand for labor, and thus wage rates, and also
serve to increase the supply of consumers’ goods and
thereby reduce their prices. (They increase the
supply of consumers' goods by equipping the average
worker with more and better capital goods, which
increases his ability to produce.)
The principal obstacle in the way of saving and
capital accumulation and thus the rise in real wages
is government welfare-state spending. It is what
necessitates the taxes, budget deficits, and
inflation of the money supply that deprives business
of the funds with which to pay wages and buy capital
goods. (Inflation can provide everyone with more
money. But it cannot provide enough additional money
to enable business firms to replace their assets
after paying taxes on the overstated profits that it
causes.)
Finally, whoever wants to raise the wages of the
average worker must oppose the massive and
ever-growing body of government regulation that
serves to raise costs of production. Contrary to the
naive view of the left, increases in costs do not
come for very long at the expense of profits. If
they did, profits would long since have disappeared.
Instead the general rate of profit remains more or
less the same. Increases in cost serve either to
raise prices or to reduce wage rates, or both. They
are the enemy of the standard of living of the
average person. Ignorant fanatics who are
responsible for causing them in the pursuit of this
or that allegedly benevolent social reform—whether
it be safety legislation, day care, maternity leave,
or whatever—are in fact the enemies of the average
worker. In the last analysis, they cause him to earn
less and pay more.
When it comes to economic understanding, the
mentality of
The New York Times and of the left in
general is one of soft, mushy ignorance encased in
an impenetrable shell of super-hardened
self-righteous ignorance. It is on the basis of such
a mentality that it seeks to foment class warfare.
Copyright ©
2006 by George Reisman. All rights reserved.
George
Reisman, Ph.D., is the author of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books, 1996) and is
Pepperdine University Professor Emeritus of
Economics.
Tuesday, August 22, 2006
More from Böhm-Bawerk
on Cost of Production as a Determinant of Prices
The following adds to my
previous post
about what Böhm-Bawerk says concerning the
explanatory role of cost of production in Austrian
economics. The quotation is from his essay
“Value, Cost, and
Marginal Utility,”
(trans. George Reisman,
Quarterly Journal
of Austrian Economics, vol. 5, no. 3,
pp. 43-44).
[I]n order to rule out every doubt and every
misunderstanding, I want to make a few explicit
declarations:
(1) We too [i.e., we “marginal-value theorists,” as
he describes his school, i.e., we Austrian
economists—GR] fully recognize the sway of a “law of
costs” for goods that are reproducible at will.
“There is a law of costs”—I once wrote—“costs
exercise an important influence on the value of
goods.”[18] “That costs of production of goods
exercise an important influence on their value is a
fact so well verified by experience that it
absolutely cannot be doubted.”[19] “One is in fact
correct, when one says that costs govern value.”[20]
(2) We too recognize the necessity of
“supplementing” the universal law of marginal
utility by means of special provisions that relate
to the value of goods reproducible at will and that
the substance of these is precisely the law of
costs. And we have accomplished this "supplementing”
in full detail, both for the field of subjective
value and for that of objective value and
prices.[21]
(3) We too understand the law of costs in such a way
that we ascribe to the height of the costs of
production, that is to say, to the value of the
means of production, the status of a cause—though,
to be sure only an intermediate cause—in relation to
the value of those products to which the law of
costs generally applies. “In our present case (that
of goods reproducible at will and of higher direct
marginal utility), the value of the product must
accommodate itself” (to the value of the means of
production). “The value of products of higher direct
marginal utility. . . comes to them from the side of
the means of production.”[22]
(4) In connection with this, we too acknowledge that
changes in the conditions of producing goods
reproducible at will never fail to bring about a
change in the value of those goods and, to be sure,
even without a change in the supply of finished
products necessarily having to take place.[23]
[18] “Grundzüge der Theorie des wirtschaftlichen
Güterwerts,” new series, vol. 13, p. 73.
[19] Ibid. p. 61.
[20] Ibid. p. 71.
[21] “Grundzüge,” pp. 61ff., 534ff.
Positive Theorie
des Kapitals
(Innsbruck, 1889), pp. 189ff. and esp. pp. 234ff.
[The material referred to appears in English
translation in Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk,
Capital and
Interest, 3 vols., trans. George D.
Huncke and Hans F. Sennholz (South Holland, Ill.:
Libertarian Press, 1959), vol. 2, pp. 168–76 and
248–56. Vol. 2, pp. 173–76 are on line at
http://www.capitalism.net/excerpts/boehm_q.htm.]
[22] “Grundzüge,” p. 70.
[23] Thus, for example, on one occasion, Wieser
says: “Cases of the kind last discussed are
conspicuous in that the effect of cost on the value
of the products takes place without the quantity of
products being affected” (Der
naturliche Wert [Vienna, 1889], p. 171;
[Natural Value
(1893; New York: Kelley and Millman, 1956), p. 178.
(In the QJAE,
Natural Value is mistakenly rendered
Natural Law.)])
The above footnote references to
Grundzüge
can now be found in an English-language translation
of that volume. The translation is titled
Basic Principles
of Economic Value, trans. Hans Sennholz
(Grove City, Pennsylvania: Libertarian Press, 2005).
The footnote references are to pp. 79, 67, 77,
67-80, 161-167, and 76-77, respectively. There are
some generally minor differences between my
translation of the sentences quoted by Böhm-Bawerk
and their translation by Prof. Sennholz.
I consider it extremely unfortunate that neither
Rothbard nor Mises explicitly deals with this very
important aspect of Böhm-Bawerk’s writings, which I
consider to be one of his major contributions to
economic thought. Its inclusion, in my judgment,
would have considerably enriched their discussions
of prices. Mises did, however, implicitly endorse
Böhm-Bawerk’s views on the subject when, immediately
after singling out the latter’s
Capital and
Interest, he wrote: “These masterful
expositions are unsatisfactory in some minor points
and disfigured by unsuitable expressions. But they
are essentially irrefutable. As far as they need to
be amended, it must be done by a consistent
elaboration of the fundamental thoughts of their
authors rather than by a refutation of their
reasoning.” [Human
Action, 3d ed. rev. (Chicago: Henry
Regnery Company, 1966), p. 201.]
Böhm-Bawerk’s treatment of cost and its relationship
to marginal utility and price is a very prominent
feature of
Capital and Interest: it occupies the
whole of two chapters in Book III of Volume II,
which is titled “Value and Price,” namely, Chapter
VII of Part A and Chapter IV of Part B; it also
occupies the whole of Excursus VIII in Volume III.
Mises must certainly have meant to include this
material in his endorsement; it certainly could not
be described as “minor points” or “unsuitable
expressions.”
Beyond this, I was in the fortunate position of
learning more of Mises’s views on the subject of the
role cost and of his endorsement of Böhm-Bawerk’s
views on the subject, as the result of being a
member of his seminar at NYU. This made it possible
for me to ask him direct questions on the subject.
Specifically, I had taken a class from Prof. George
Stigler at Columbia University and learned of Dennis
Robertson’s attempt to deal with the problem of
calculating the marginal product of a tenth hole
digger in the face of the availability of only nine
shovels. Robertson’s answer, as reported by Stigler,
was that the tenth worker could be sent to fetch
beer.
I was very dissatisfied with such an answer and
began to see serious problems with efforts to derive
marginal products and marginal value products from
consumers’ goods in many cases. First, I raised the
matter with Rothbard, who referred me to various
textbooks for the solution. They did not satisfy me
any more than had Robertson’s answer. I then raised
the matter with Mises. Almost immediately, Mises
asked if I had in mind deriving the value of
original factors of production or produced factors
of production. I replied that I was concerned with
both. The value of produced factors of production,
he said, was determined by their cost of production.
This was an answer that greatly surprised me.
Because until then, I had thought that Mises and all
of sound economics totally denied any possibility of
value or price being determined by cost. Mises
referred me to
Capital and
Interest for elaboration. The specific
reference he gave was to Excursus VII, which is a
brilliant essay on the value of complimentary goods
and is closely related to Böhm-Bawerk’s views on the
subject of costs. Reading it soon led me into the
other portions of Böhm-Bawerk’s work that I’ve
cited. Mises’s directing me to Böhm-Bawerk on the
subjects of imputation and costs, of course, only
deepens what for me is the mystery of why he didn’t
explicitly incorporate this aspect of Böhm-Bawerk’s
writings into
Human Action. And as I think back now, a
mystery almost as large is why I never thought of
asking him.
Copyright ©
2006 by George Reisman. All rights reserved.
George
Reisman, Ph.D., is the author of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books, 1996) and is
Pepperdine University Professor Emeritus of
Economics.
Tuesday, August 15, 2006
The Austrian
Economics that Most of Today’s “Austrians” Don’t
Know
To the great majority of those who today consider
themselves to be supporters of Austrian economics,
any suggestion that there are cases in which the
direct, immediate determinant of price is cost of
production is likely to be greeted as though it were
indicative of such profound ignorance as to be cause
for scandal. These “Austrians” believe that the
prices of factors of production—labor, land, and
capital goods of all descriptions—are determined by
the prices of their respective products and can
never determine the prices of their products.
This, however, was not the view of two of the most
important Austrian economists of the 19th and early
20th centuries, namely, Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk and
Friedrich von Wieser, who were the two leading
disciples of Carl Menger, the founder of the
Austrian school. Böhm-Bawerk was also the teacher of
Ludwig von Mises, and was probably considered by
Mises to be the most important of all Austrian
economists, himself included. (Mises, I think, could
sometimes be unduly modest about his own enormous
accomplishments, which, in fact, surpassed those of
Böhm-Bawerk, great as the latter’s were.)
Without further ado, I am simply going to quote
Böhm-Bawerk from his masterwork
Capital and
Interest, using the same quotation I’ve
been permitted to use in my own book.
Böhm-Bawerk on How and When
Costs Determine Prices
Up to this point in our discussion the law of the
value of production goods was developed subject to
the simplifying hypothesis that every group of means
of production admits of utilization only to one very
definite purpose. That hypothesis is in real life
only very rarely in agreement with the facts. It is
preeminently production goods, far more than
consumption goods, which are characterized by
egregious heterogeneity. The overwhelming majority
of them will be capable of service in several
productive fields, some are adaptable to thousands
of such productive services. Examples are iron,
coal, and above all, human labor. Of course, we have
to take these factual circumstances into account in
conducting our theoretical investigation. We must
observe what modifications, if any, affect the law
that the value of a group of goods occupying remote
orders is governed by the value of their product.
Let us alter the order of the presuppositions of our
typical example accordingly. Someone possesses a
rather large supply of means of production of second
order (G2). From each of these groups he can produce
at will a consumption good of the category A, or one
of category B or finally, of category C. He desires,
of course, to take advance measures toward balanced
provision for his various wants, and will therefore
draw simultaneously on various parts of his supply
of means of production to produce consumption goods
of all three categories. And he will produce amounts
in each in accordance with his needs. If there is
genuinely balanced provision, the quantities
produced will be so regulated that needs of
approximately equal importance depend upon the last
specimen in each category, and that thus the
marginal utilities are approximately equal. In spite
of that it is not impossible that there will be
differences—possibly even quite considerable
differences—in the marginal utilities because, as we
already know, the gradation of concrete wants
occurring in any one category is not always either
uniform or continuous. The first stove in my room
will afford me a very considerable utility, say one
we might designate with an index of 200. A second
stove will afford no utility at all. I shall most
emphatically call a halt in providing stoves when I
have a single specimen with its marginal utility of
200, even though in other areas provision for needs
may see a dropping off of the average of marginal
utility to as little as 120 or even 100. And so it
is permissible and necessary, if our example is to
be true to nature, to assume that the marginal
utility of a specimen will be different in each of
the categories A, B and C. Let us call it 100 for A,
120 for B and 200 for C.
Now the question arises, “What is the value, under
these circumstances, of a group of means of
production, G2?”
We have had so much practice with selective
decisions of a similar nature that we can give the
answer without hesitation. The value will be equal
to 100. For if one of the available groups of means
of production should be lost, the owner would
naturally shift the loss to the least sensitive
area. He would not curtail production in category B
where he would be sacrificing a marginal utility of
120, and certainly not in category C where the
sacrifice would go as high as 200. He would quite
simply produce one specimen fewer of category A
where the reduction in well-being is only 100. Let
us express it in general terms. The value of a unit
of means of production is governed by the marginal
utility and the value of that product which has the
least marginal utility among all those products for
the making of which the unit means of production
could have justifiably been used.
All the relations which we had declared to be
plainly in force with regard to the value of means
of production and their products under the
simplifying assumption of only a single possible
disposition, are therefore generally valid as
between the value of means of production and value
of its least valuable product.
And what is the situation with respect to the other
categories of products, B and C? That question
brings us to the origin of the “law of costs.”
If under all circumstances the marginal utility
attainable by a good within its own category were
determinative, then the categories B and C would
have to receive a value divergent not only from that
of category A, but also from the value of its costs
G2. B would then have a value of 120, C a value of
200. But here we are confronted with one of the
cases where, through substitution, a possible loss
in one category is transferred to another, and as a
result, the marginal utility of the latter becomes
determinative for the other as well. Thus, if a
specimen of category C is lost, it is not necessary
to forgo the marginal utility of 200 which the
specimen would have delivered directly. Instead, it
is possible to convert one unit of the means of
production G2 into a new specimen C, and in its
place rather produce one specimen fewer in that
category in which the marginal utility, and hence
the loss in utility is least. And indeed that
possibility becomes a reality. The category in
question in our example is the category A. Because
of the opportunity which production offers for
substitution, a specimen C is therefore not valued
in accordance with its own marginal utility of 200,
but in accordance with the marginal utility of the
least valuable related product, the product A; its
value is therefore 100. The same applies, naturally,
to the value of category B, and would apply
generally to every category of good which is
“productionally related” to A, and of which the
direct marginal utility is also greater than that of
category A.
This leads to some important consequences. The first
is that in this way the value of goods having a
higher individual marginal utility occupies the same
rank as the value of the “marginal product”; and
hence also the same rank as the means of production from which both
emanate. The identity which exists in principle
between “value” and “costs” therefore obtains in
this instance as well. But it is to be
carefully noted that here the coinciding is brought
about in quite a different way from that which was
followed in the case of costs and marginal product.
In the latter instance the two coincide because the
value of the means of production accommodates itself
to the value of the product. The value of the
product is the determinant factor, the means of
production is the factor that is determined. In our
present case it is the other way around, and it is
the value of the
product
that must do the accommodating. Ultimately it
accommodates only to the value of another product.
But initially it accommodates also to the value of
the means of production from which it emanates and
which brings about its substitutional connection
with the marginal product. The transmission of value
proceeds, so to speak, along a broken line. First it
goes from the marginal product to the means of
production, fixes the value of the latter, and then
ascends in the opposite direction from the means of
production to the other products which it is
possible to produce from them. In the end product,
then, the products of higher immediate marginal
utility derive their value from their means of
production. Let us translate the abstract formula
into terms of concrete practice. Good B or good C
is, in general, a product of higher immediate
marginal utility. If now we consider what good B or
C is worth to us our first response is, “Just
exactly as much as the means of production are worth
to us from which we can at any moment replace the
product.” If we then inquire further and ask how
much the means of production themselves are worth,
we arrive at the marginal utility of the marginal
product A. But on innumerable occasions we can spare
ourselves this further inquiry. Time and again we
already know the value of the goods that comprise
the cost, without any necessity for working it out
from its foundation and proceeding onward from case
to case. And on all these occasions we simply
determine the value of products by their costs, and
in doing so we are taking advantage of an
abbreviation which is as accurate as it is
convenient.
And now the whole truth about the celebrated law of
costs is revealed. It is indeed quite correct to say
that costs govern value. Only it is imperative to
remain aware of the limits within which this “law”
is valid and of the source from which it derives its
virtues. In the first place it is only a particular
law. It is valid only so long as the possibility is
present of furnishing, through production,
substitute specimens in any quantity and at any time
they are desired. If there is no possibility of
substitution, then in the case of each product,
value must be determined by its immediate marginal
utility in its own category. In that case its value
no longer coincides with that of the marginal
product and of the intermediate means of production.
Therein lies the explanation of the empirically
established principle that the law of costs is valid
only for the goods that are “reproducible at will,”
and that it is a law of only approximate validity.
For it does not bind the goods over which it holds
sway to slavishly meticulous adherence to costs. On
the contrary, it permits fluctuations above and
below such costs, depending on whether production at
the moment lags behind demand or outstrips it.
A second and still more important consideration is
that even where the law of costs is valid, those
costs are not the final, but only an intermediate
cause of the value of goods. In the last analysis,
they do not give value to their products, but
receive it from them. That is clear as crystal in
the case of production goods for which there is only
one productive use. Surely no one will wish to deny
that it would be erroneous to assert that Tokay wine
is valuable because Tokay vineyards possess value;
everyone will concede that the truth is the other
way around, and those vineyards have a high value
because their product is highly valued. It is just
as hopeless to deny that the value of a quicksilver
mine depends on that of the quicksilver, the value
of a wheatfield on that of wheat, the value of a
brickkiln on that of brick, and not vice versa. Only
because of the manysidedness of most cost goods is
it possible for the situation to present the
opposite appearance. As the moon reflects the light
of the sun upon the earth, so do the manysided cost
goods reflect the value which they receive from
their marginal product on their other products. (Eugen
von Böhm-Bawerk,
Capital and
Interest. 3 vols., Sennholz and Huncke
translation (South Holland, Illinois [Grove City,
Pennsylvania]: Libertarian Press, 1959), vol. 2, pp.
173-176. Quoted with permission of Libertarian
Press. See also ibid., vol. 3, Excursus 8, and
Böhm-Bawerk’s article “Value, Cost, and Marginal
Utility,” George Reisman, trans.,
Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics,
vol. 5, no. 3,
pp. 43-45.
As I wrote in
Capitalism, what Böhm-Bawerk has shown
in these passages is that when the price of goods
whose own, direct marginal utility is extremely high
is determined on the basis of cost of production,
precisely then
is its value determined on the basis of marginal
utility—the marginal utility of the
means of production used to produce it, as
determined in other, less important employments. The
buyer of an automobile fan belt or any other
essential automotive part, for example, does not pay
a price corresponding to the value he attaches to
his car, but a much lower price corresponding to the
marginal utility of the materials and labor required
to produce fan belts or whatever—a marginal utility
that in turn is determined by the marginal utility
of products other than fan belts or whatever. As
Böhm-Bawerk develops the law of diminishing marginal
utility, it is no more surprising that the price of
vital components and parts, or any necessity, is in
conformity with its cost of production rather than
its own direct marginal utility than it is that the
marginal utility of the water on which our physical
survival depends is no greater than the utility of
the marginal quantity of water we use. Determination
of price by cost is merely a mechanism by means of
which the value of supramarginal products is reduced
to the value of marginal products. The only
complication is that the marginal products in this
case are physically different and lie in other lines
of production.
Here I must add that Böhm-Bawerk’s demonstration has
the potential to accomplish two very major results:
One, is to overthrow the core of contemporary
“microeconomics” and its fixation on “marginal
revenue” and the concomitant alleged ability of all
significant sized firms to exploit marginal revenue
at the expense of consumers. Böhm-Bawerk’s doctrine
implies that wherever there is legal freedom of
entry into an industry, the concept of marginal
revenue becomes largely irrelevant. Price will be
determined on the basis of cost, irrespective of the
degree of inelasticity of demand and potential
willingness of buyers to pay higher prices.
The second major result is a very substantial
narrowing of the gap that is perceived as separating
Austrian economics from British classical economics.
As I’ve shown throughout
Capitalism,
there is enormous value in classical economics that
has been overlooked for no genuinely good reason. If
what is of value in classical economics could be
added to the already great strengths of Austrian
economics, the result would be a far more powerful
defense of economic freedom and assault on statist
intervention than is now possible.
But the most important, the overriding and
sufficient reason for accepting Böhm-Bawerk’s
analysis here is simply that it is profoundly
enlightening—it’s the enlightenment yielded by the
principle of marginal utility all over again, on a
higher plane.
The quotation from Böhm-Bawerk in this article is
copyright © 1959 by Libertarian Press and may not be
reproduced without the permission of
Libertarian Press.
The remainder of this article is copyright © 2006,
by George Reisman. All rights reserved. George
Reisman is the author of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books, 1996) and is
Pepperdine University Professor Emeritus of
Economics.
Monday, August 14, 2006
Mining for the Next
Million Years
For many years, I’ve been pointing out that the
entire mass of the earth, from the upper limits of
its atmosphere 4,000 miles straight down to its
core, consists of nothing but solidly packed
chemical elements. There is not one cubic centimeter
anywhere in the earth’s mass that is not some
chemical element or other, or some combination of
chemical elements. This, I’ve said, is nature’s
contribution to the supply of natural resources,
along with all of the enormous quantities of energy
that go with it, from the energy contained in fossil
fuels, uranium, wind, water, and the earth’s core to
the energy contained in thunderstorms and static
electricity.
How much of this immense quantity of matter and
energy can be transformed into the narrower category
of natural resources that are economically useable
by and accessible to man depends on the state of
science, technology, and supply of capital
equipment. In other words, it depends on the extent
of man’s knowledge of nature and the degree of his
physical power over it. As man enlarges this
knowledge and power, he increases the fraction of
nature that constitutes economically useable,
accessible natural resources. In the process, he
transforms what had up to then been mere
nature-given things into economic goods and wealth.
I’ve also always pointed out that up to now our
power over nature—our ability to actually get at its
contents and direct them to the satisfaction of our
needs—has been measured in depths of feet rather
than miles and has essentially been confined just to
the thirty percent or so of the earth’s surface that
is land. The clear implication is that we are still
at the very beginning of our ability to extract
economically useable natural resources from nature.
I’ve now gathered some empirical data that indicates
just how modest man’s mining activities actually are
compared to the size of the earth. For example,
total global production of petroleum is
approximately
30 billion barrels
per year.
Each barrel of petroleum measures approximately
.16 of a cubic
meter.
This means that in terms of cubic meters, the
physical volume of all the petroleum extracted in
the world in a year is .16 times 30 billion, which
is 4.8 billion cubic meters. Since a thousand meters
equals 1 kilometer, a billion cubic meters
translates into a mere 1 cubic kilometer. So the
physical volume of total annual global petroleum
production is presently 4.8 cubic kilometers. And
because 1 cubic mile equals approximately 4.17 cubic
kilometers, this means that all of the world’s
petroleum production in a year represents about 1.15
cubic miles.
All by itself, this is enough to suggest that total
global mining operations are extremely small
relative to the size of the earth, which is
1.1 trillion
cubic kilometers,
or approximately
260 billion
cubic miles.
This conclusion is confirmed when one considers the
global annual production of other important
minerals, such as iron ore, coal, aluminum, and
natural gas.
Global iron ore production was approximately
1.16 billion
metric tons in 2003,
the most recent year for which data are readily
available. The density of iron ore varies between
approximately
4 metric tons per
cubic meter and 5 metric tons per cubic meter,
depending on the type of ore. The smaller the number
of metric tons per cubic meter, the larger the
number of cubic meters required for any given
tonnage. Using the lower figure of 4 metric tons per
cubic meter, the total cubic volume of iron ore
production in 2003 would be 291 million cubic
meters, which is .291 cubic kilometers or .07 cubic
miles. Because much of the iron ore extracted had a
higher density, the actual physical volume of iron
ore extracted was considerably less.
Global coal production in 2005 was
5.84 billion
metric tons.
Since the density of coal is roughly
1.3 metric tons per cubic meter,
the physical volume of the coal extracted was about
4.5 cubic kilometers, or about 1.08 cubic miles.
Global aluminum production in 2001 was
32 million metric
tons.
The production of 1 ton of aluminum requires the
mining of 4 to 6 tons of bauxite. Thus 32 million
tons of aluminum production implies the mining of as
much as 192 million tons of bauxite. Inasmuch as the
density of bauxite is
1.28 metric tons per cubic meter,
the cubic volume of the total amount of bauxite
mined in 2001 was 150 million cubic meters. This in
turn equals .15 cubic kilometers, or less than .04
of a cubic mile.
Global dry natural gas production in 2004 was
approximately
98.62 trillion
cubic feet,
which equals 2,774 cubic kilometers. To put this
figure in perspective, it should be realized that
when liquefied, the volume of natural gas is
reduced by a factor of 600.
Thus the equivalent of this much gas in liquid form
is 4.62 cubic kilometers, or a little over 1.1 cubic
miles. This, of course, is somewhat less than the
cubic volume of petroleum production.
If we add up these numbers, they total 14.28 cubic
kilometers or 3.42 cubic miles. To allow both for
the mining of everything else and for any
extractions we may have overlooked in connection
with the items we’ve considered, let’s just assume
the nice round number of 100 cubic kilometers or
roughly 24 cubic miles as representing all current
mining operations combined on an annual basis for
the world as a whole.
In a tolerably free, rational society, motivated
human intelligence is easily capable not only of
continuing man’s ability to extract this volume of
useful materials from the earth but also
substantially to increase it. If the present annual
volume of such extractions were merely to continue,
it could do so at least for the next 100 million
years. By that time, a total of 10 billion cubic
kilometers or roughly 2.4 billion cubic miles of
earth would have been extracted, which would
represent a little less than 1 percent of the
earth’s total physical volume. If economic progress
in coming centuries serves to increase the annual
rate of extractions by a factor of 100, then mining
operations could continue on that vastly larger
scale for a million years, before 1 percent of the
earth’s volume had been extracted. The exhaustion of
useable, accessible mineral deposits is simply not a
problem for an economy as free as that of the United
States was until a few generations ago.
Our growing problems in connection with the supply
of natural resources are not caused by nature but by
us. We have allowed ourselves to abandon our reason
and give up our freedom. We have allowed ourselves
to be led by people who would have us freeze and be
immobilized rather than spill some oil on snow
hardly any of us will ever see or disturb the
habitat of wild animals that mean nothing to us. If
we allow this to continue, then where we are headed
is to a world describable by these terrible words of
despair:
You must know that the world has grown old, and does
not remain in its former vigour. It bears witness to
its own decline. The rainfall and the sun’s warmth
are both diminishing; the metals are nearly
exhausted; the husbandman is failing in the fields,
the sailor on the seas, the soldier in the camp,
honesty in the market, justice in the courts,
concord in friendships, skill in the arts,
discipline in morals. This is the sentence passed
upon the world, that everything which has a
beginning should perish, that things which have
reached maturity should grow old, the strong weak,
the great small, and that after weakness and
shrinkage should come dissolution.[1]
As I wrote in
Capitalism, that passage is not a
quotation from some contemporary environmentalist or ecologist. It was written in the
third century—long
before the first chunk of coal, drop of oil, ounce
of aluminum, or any significant quantity of any
mineral whatever had been taken from the earth. Then
as now, the problem was not physical, but
philosophical and political. Then as now, men were
turning away from reason and toward mysticism. Then
as now, they were growing less free and falling ever
more under the rule of physical force. That is why
they believed, and that is why people in our culture
are beginning to believe, that man is helpless
before physical nature. There is no helplessness in
fact. To men who use reason and are free to act,
nature gives more and more. To those who turn away
from reason or are not free, it gives less and less.
Nothing else is involved.
[1] The passage quoted above appears In W. T. Jones,
The Medieval
Mind, vol. 2 of
A History of
Western Philosophy, 2d ed. (New York:
Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1969), p. 6
Copyright ©
2006 by George Reisman. All rights reserved.
George
Reisman, Ph.D., is the author of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books, 1996) and is
Pepperdine University Professor Emeritus of
Economics.
Monday, August 07, 2006
Free-Market
Science vs. Government Science
In a free market, science originates in the minds of
individual scientists, who have studied and thought
about problems that interest them and who from time
to time arrive at new insights, which they develop
further and verify. In the course of their work and
in the dissemination of its results, they often need
more funds than they can personally provide. In such
cases, inspired by the value they see in their work,
they attempt to obtain the necessary funds from
those other individuals whom they can persuade to
share their understanding of their work and its
value.
In a free market, the main source of funds would be
wealthy businessmen and wealthy heirs. In a free
market, there would be no income or inheritance
taxes, both of which are a violation of the freedom
of the individual to spend his own wealth as he
chooses. And because there would be no income or
inheritance taxes, there would be no need for the
establishment of foundations and trusts as means of
avoiding these taxes, nor for the appointment of
trustees or anyone else with power to determine the
use of one’s funds. There would thus simply be
wealthy businessmen and heirs in full control of
their own funds. And a businessman would not have to
worry about running afoul of any regulatory agency
agency that might use its power to harm his business
in retaliation for his supporting research that was
unpopular.
The possession of substantial wealth by single
individuals, with full power to determine its use,
is of vital importance. This is because not only do
new ideas originate in the minds just of single
individuals, who necessarily must set out completely
alone in any quest to change the understanding of
the rest of mankind, but the change in other
people’s understanding, which must subsequently be
brought about, also proceeds just one mind at a
time.
For an individual to understand something that is
new and significant is not an easy or automatic task
even in the best of circumstances. For the original
discoverer it must be somewhat daunting to think
that there is a significant truth that as yet, in
the entire world and in the entire history of the
world, he alone understands. Such an individual
needs to have considerable confidence in the power
and reliability of his mind. Galileo, Newton,
Pasteur, Edison—all the great innovators in science
and invention have necessarily been in this
position.
The first people to be persuaded of the truth and
significance of a new discovery, after the
discoverer himself, must also have considerable
confidence in the power and reliability of their
minds as well. Their situation is that as yet only
they and the discoverer understand this truth and
its value. They must be prepared to proceed on the
basis of no foundation but that of their own,
independent judgment that the discovery is in fact
true and valuable.
In this connection, it should be realized that even
the utmost obviousness of a truth is never a
guarantee of its acceptance by an individual. There
are many people so doubtful of their own capacity to
judge the truth, so fearful of the possible need to
defend it in a conflict with others, who they expect
will disagree, that their response even to an
extremely obvious but not yet generally recognized
truth is, in effect, that it need not be true
because if it were, it would already be generally
recognized and accepted. For such people, the
ability to recognize the truth melts away without
the assurance that practically everyone else is
prepared to confirm the truth as true. Only then can
acceptance of a truth be sufficiently separated from
the possibility of conflict with others that it can
take place without being blocked by fear.
Consider, for example, how the great mass of people
could once go on believing, century after century,
that the world was flat. Certainly that was how the
world appeared to them any time they looked out at a
broad expanse of land in front of them. But some
people in this period knew that the world was round
and that its appearance of flatness could easily be
reconciled with the fact of its roundness.
The conclusion that the world was round was an
obvious inference to be drawn from such facts as the
tops of the masts of sailing vessels appearing on
the horizon first, followed by more and more of the
masts, and then by the body of the vessels, as they
came closer. It was an obvious inference to be drawn
from the knowledge that while one could see only so
far when one looked out at the land in front of one,
the limit of one’s field of vision was not the limit
of the extent of the earth, which went further.
Curvature of the earth was the obvious explanation
in both cases.
While some people undoubtedly did understood this
much at the time, most people could not be persuaded
of it for many centuries. They were essentially
immune to this knowledge. Whether is was simply out
of fear of conflict with others to whom they might
have to explain it in the face of resistance and
possible derision, or simply a matter of
intellectual laziness on their part, or both, the
essential fact is that here was a very simple truth
that the great majority of mankind could not be
gotten to accept for a very long time. And even
today, when virtually everyone finally does
acknowledge that the earth is round, it is probably
the case that a large proportion of the people who
now do so, have no better reason for doing so than
that this is what they know the great majority of
people believe and is thus what they are expected to
believe.
Intellectually inert and fearful people continue to
be extremely numerous. They are to be found at all
levels of educational attainment. Those with higher
levels of education simply know more about what most
people supposedly believe and that they are thus
expected to believe. They hold their knowledge
virtually as a collection of public opinion polls.
Very little if any of their ostensible knowledge is
solidly grounded. They have little or no basis for
forming an independent judgment of the truth or
falsity of new knowledge.
Such people are so numerous that even in relatively
small groups one or more of them can be expected to
be found. This is what makes it so important that
the power to make decisions rests in the hands of
single individuals, not groups, committees, or
boards of any kind. To the extent that it is groups,
committees, or boards that decide, the likely
presence of such people and their mutual
reinforcement of each other constitutes a major
obstacle in the way of a valuable new idea going
forward.
The advancement of science depends on a free market,
because the free market and its vesting of
decision-making power in the hands of single
individuals rather than groups is able to shunt
aside those who lack the power of independent
judgment. They are relegated to the sidelines, where
they can enjoy all the benefits of scientific and
economic progress but not get in its way.
Now let us turn to science under the tutelage of the
state.
State control of science is the attempt to combine
opposites. In essence, science is mind; the state is
physical force. Science makes its way by means of
the voluntary assent of the individual human mind to
its recognition of truth. In contrast, the state and
what the state sponsors makes its way by means of
the use of physical force and the threat of physical
force. There is no law, regulation, ruling, edict,
or decree made by the state that is not backed by
the threat of physical force to compel obedience to
it. The state does not say to the individual do or
do not do this because of its reasonableness or lack
of reasonableness, and take as long as you like
before coming around to our position. No. It says,
do this or do not do this if you want to stay out of
jail and avoid being injured or killed in resisting.
Any financial support the state may provide to
science is by means of taxes collected at the point
of a gun, from people who know that they will be
imprisoned if they do not pay the taxes and injured
or killed if they resist being imprisoned. This is a
remarkable foundation for the progress of science,
much like a purported construction of a laboratory
by gorillas.
Thus, the starting point of state-sponsored science
is the exact opposite of the starting point of
actual science: it is physical force not the
voluntary assent of the individual mind.
There is another important difference in starting
point. Science begins in the mind of the individual
scientist seeking important truth not previously
identified. State-sponsored science in contrast
typically begins with an already established
consensus
concerning the subject to be pursued. This is
because the existence of a consensus increases the
likelihood of being able to obtain political support
for the project.
Of course, not all state-sponsored science requires
an existing consensus. Stalin did not need a
consensus when he decided to promote the career of
the biologist Lysenko, because of the latter’s
support for the theory of acquired characteristics.
The example of Stalin and Lysenko sheds light on the
kind of scientific quest that any politician or
government official will initiate if he can. Because
the primary concern of such a person is always the
maintenance and enhancement of his power, the
projects he initiates will be projects designed to
increase his power and prestige. Any connection with
scientific truth is likely to be merely
coincidental. Thus in the case of Stalin and
Lysenko, the objective was not the promotion of the
science of biology, but support, wrung at the
expense of the science of biology, for the Marxist
doctrine that life under Communist rule could change
human nature by virtue of a succession of
generations acquiring characteristics that would
then be genetically transmitted to later
generations.
Whether state-sponsored science rests on an existing
consensus or on the initiative of an individual
politician, it differs radically from genuine
science in yet another respect. This concerns the
relationship between science and money. In a free
market, it is the truth and importance of the
science that drives the raising of money. Money is
raised in order to facilitate the development and
dissemination of the science. Money is the means;
science is the end. With state-sponsored science,
this relationship is largely reversed.
The state, in effect, offers pots of money in the
form of “grants” for the study of matters selected
by politicians and their appointees, and then
scientists must choose areas of investigation that
are most likely to secure them some of that money.
The “scientists” gather around the pots of money,
like bees around pots of honey, eagerly seeking as
best they can to slurp up some of the money by means
of writing whatever kind of grant proposals they
think will promote the agenda of whichever officials
have the power to determine the award of the grants.
The meaning of this state of affairs is that the
initiative for science passes from scientists to the
state, i.e., to politicians and their appointees.
And instead of money serving science, science now
serves money, and, it must be stressed, not ordinary
money, but money collected at the point of a gun,
and made available on conditions determined by
politicians and the appointees of politicians.
In a free market, of course,
applied
science serves money. There are companies that want
to develop specific products and they employ
scientists to help develop them. But the funds are
raised voluntarily and the applied science must be
true, or the products will not work. There are also
companies and wealthy individuals in a free market
who may be interested in the exploration of various
fields of basic science and who offer monetary
incentives to scientists to pursue such research.
Again, at the very least, the relationship is
strictly voluntary.
What is crucial is that in a free market, there is
room for independent scientists, scientists who themselves
take the initiative in their work and who, thanks
largely to the existence of a substantial number of
wealthy businessmen and heirs, have a real chance of
obtaining the funds they need in order to pursue
their work and disseminate its results. Indeed, in a
free market, without income taxes, there might well
be significant financial support for independent
science extending deep into the ranks of the middle
class.
State-sponsored science comes into existence on a
large scale in an environment in which the
foundations of genuine basic science are already
largely undercut by the existence of progressive
income and inheritance taxes and an accompanying
collectivization even of private decision making:
i.e. the replacement of individual decision making
with decision making by groups of various kinds,
notably boards and committees.
Once state support of science comes into existence,
there is little prospect of major advances in
science gaining any support from it. A major advance
in science represents the radically new and
different. However true it may be, its truth as yet
lacks adherents. And precisely for this reason, it
is almost certain to be rejected by those whose
standard of truth is acceptance by others. It does
not yet and cannot yet have this acceptance because
of its very newness. If it is to be accepted, it
must be accepted on the basis of independent
judgment and nothing else. But the exercise of
independent
judgment virtually cries out for the
foundation of the ownership of
independent wealth.
Independent, i.e., privately owned, wealth, can be
used in support of the radically new and different.
In that case if the judgment is wrong, the loss is
that of the person who made it. But when the wealth
being used is publicly owned, then whoever makes the
judgment concerning its use, must above all be sure
that he can prove that he did absolutely nothing out
of the ordinary with it. Only in that way, can he
avoid blame for any loss.
State-funded science is necessarily a swamp of
mediocrity. It is the domain of peer-reviewed
journal articles and of statistical studies. In
peer-reviewed journals, nothing is considered worthy
of publication unless deemed to be so by “peers.”
What this means is that in order for a radical new
idea to be accepted for publication, it must
immediately gain the support of those who hold the
opposing, now outmoded ideas that it shows to be in
error, or else it cannot be published. Such an
arrangement is tantamount to requiring that before
Galileo can publish, his ideas must have the
endorsement of astronomers who up to the moment of
reading him have adhered to the Ptolemaic system of
astronomy. It is tantamount to requiring that before
Louis Pasteur can publish on the subject of the germ
theory of disease, he must have the assent of those
who deny the very existence of germs.
State-funded science is very much at home with
statistical studies. This is because they can all be
made to fit easily specified criteria with respect
to such matters as sample size, confidence
intervals, and confidence levels. They are thus a
very good way for large numbers of “scientists” to
be kept employed attempting to establish or deny the
likelihood of a relationship existing between
practically any two things in the universe. Provided
the “scientist” can verify that he has followed the
rules of such a study, he can rely on keeping his
government grant check and go on to the next “study”
and the next government grant.
Perhaps some may find the most telling criticism of
state-funded science the simple visualization of
the faces of various politicians and government
officials, coupled with the realization that it is
they who are now in charge of science. Even though
our President, his Cabinet officers, and our
legislators do not personally award government grant
money, they might as well do so. This is because it
is still their judgment, such as it is, that
determines the appointment of those who do award the
grants, or the appointment of those who whose
further job it is to make such appointments. And in
the same way, with whatever intervening layers of
appointees that there may be, it is their judgment
that ultimately underlies the choice of all members
of the government’s panels of science advisors.
There is first of all the very great problem of the
ability of our politicians and officials to make any
kind of sound appointments. Who are they, after all?
What is it that they actually know about science, or
about anything for that matter? What qualifies them
to determine the qualifications of an appointee? And
then there is the further problem of who is it that
seeks out such jobs as determining the award of
government grant money? Who is it who seeks
appointment to the government’s advisory panels of
scientists?
Serious scientists are concerned with the pursuit of
science, not the politics of science. It is not
likely that they will be interested in obtaining
such positions. Such positions are sought precisely
by the opposite kind of “scientists,” namely, those
for whom it is the politics of science that counts,
and not the actual substance of science. These are
the kind of people who actually enjoy being members
of committees. And it is these people, several rungs
down in the bureaucratic hierarchy, who are now the
masters of science on a day-to-day basis.
State-sponsored science is the destroyer of science.
If science is to live, government funding of science
must end.
Copyright ©
2006 by George Reisman. All rights reserved.
George
Reisman, Ph.D., is the author of
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics
(Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books, 1996) and is
Pepperdine University Professor Emeritus of
Economics.