Monday, July 31, 2006
Wage Rates and Purchasing Power
An individual who
earns more money per week is obviously in a position
to spend more in buying consumers’ goods than is an
individual who earns less money per week. For
example, a man who makes $1,000 per week has the
ability to spend $1,000 per week, while a man who
makes only $900 per week has the ability to spend
only $900 per week. (For the sake of simplicity,
we’re ignoring such possibilities as going into debt
or using up savings, and assuming that the
individuals both want to live within their incomes.)
When there is unemployment and free-market
economists urge the freedom of wage rates to fall as
the means of eliminating the unemployment, many
people think of examples like the above and conclude
that the free-market solution would only serve to
make matters worse. They reason, in effect, that now
workers who had been earning $1,000 per week would
only earn $900 per week and thus be reduced to
spending only $900 per week instead of $1,000 per
week. Generalizing from this example to wage
reductions of any size, and to their effect across
the whole economic system, people conclude that
wage-rate reductions cause reductions in overall
consumer spending and therefore must serve to make
the problem of unemployment worse, rather than
better. In fact, often going under the name of
Keynesianism, this is far and away the prevailing
doctrine on the subject and is why reductions in
wage rates are rarely if ever advocated as the means
of reducing unemployment in the present-day world.
However, let us approach matters now not from the
perspective of an individual wage earner, but from
that of the economic system as a whole, essentially
just like Henry Hazlitt did in his brilliant
Economics In One Lesson.
In the economic system as a whole, in any given
year, there’s a certain overall total amount of
payroll expenditures by business firms, i.e., a
certain overall total amount of wage payments.
There’s also a certain overall total amount of
consumer spending that takes place in the year.
Since it‘s always essential to think in terms of
numbers when dealing with such matters, let’s assume
that in the economic system as a whole in a given
year total payroll expenditures amount to 400 units
of money. (This is certainly a very small number of
units, but each unit can be understood as
representing as many billions or tens of billions of
dollars as may be necessary for the 400 units to
represent the actual total payrolls of the
present-day United States. Thinking in terms of a
small number of units allows us to avoid wasting
valuable brain space in holding strings of
unnecessary zeros in our minds)
Let’s also assume that total annual spending to buy
consumers goods in this economic system is 500 units
of money, with each unit of money representing as
many billions or tens of billions of dollars as does
each of the 400 units of money paid as wages.
So here we are: 400 units of money is total wage
payments and 500 units of money is total consumer
spending in our hypothetical economic system.
We can assume that 400 of the 500 of consumer
spending represents consumption expenditure by wage
earners, out of their 400 of wage incomes. The
remaining 100 of consumer spending can be taken as
representing consumption by businessmen and
capitalists, out of profits, interest, and
dividends, and/or out of previously accumulated
capital.
Now imagine that in this hypothetical economic
system, there is 10 percent unemployment. That means
that there is also 90 percent, positive employment.
Going from 10 percent unemployment to full
employment means increasing positive employment in
the ratio of 10 to 9.
Isn’t it clear that if total payroll spending were
maintained, a 10 percent reduction in wage rates
would secure full employment? That it would mean
10/9 the workers employed at 9/10 the average wage.
Wouldn’t consumer spending also hold up in these
circumstances, with 10/9 the workers spending 9/10
the average wage per worker?
And if the output per worker remained the same,
wouldn’t the same total consumer spending of 500
units of money be sufficient to buy 10/9 the output
at 9/10 the prices? And wouldn’t total profit in the
economic system, and, by implication, the average
rate of profit, be the same, despite the fall in
prices? (Wouldn’t total profit essentially continue
to be 500 units of money in the form of consumption
expenditure minus 400 units of money in the form of
wage payments?)
What of real wages? If prices and wage rates both
fall to the same extent, wouldn’t real wage rates be
the same? In fact, wouldn’t real
take-home wage rates actually increase
because of the elimination of the burden of
supporting the unemployed, who would now be employed
and supporting themselves?
And notice the implication for how real wage rates
can continually be further increased, namely, simply
by virtue of labor becoming more and more productive
and thus progressively increasing the supply of
consumers’ goods relative to the supply of labor,
thereby more and more reducing prices relative to
wage rates.
This example, of 400 of wage payments and 500 of
consumer spending, is a depiction of the economic
world in terms of essentials. Mises would call it an
imaginary construction. It is very highly
simplified. Yet it is also extremely pregnant with
implications: for employment/unemployment, for real
wages, for profit/interest, and for much else
besides.
Whoever starts to think about this example will have
many questions, the answers to which obviously
cannot be fitted into a brief article such as this.
The questions can concern such things as the effects
of adding the buying and selling of capital goods
into the example, the effects of allowing for
changes in the amount of spending in the economic
system and for changes in the relationship between
different kinds of spending, and more. For answers
to all such questions, I invite those interested to
read my book
Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics.
There I think they will find not only just about all
of the answers they are looking for, but also many
questions they have not thought of asking, along
with the answers to those questions as well.
Monday, July 24, 2006
How Environmentalism Raises Profits
at the Expense of Wages
In my last article,
“How Government
Budget Deficits Reduce Wages and Raise Profits,”
I explained why those who complain about profits
rising at the expense of wages should not blame the
free market but, in part at least, the growth in
government budget deficits. I’d now like to show
that in addition they should blame the environmental
movement and the government intervention that it has
inspired.
Environmentalism operates systematically to withhold
land and natural resources from the market. Wherever
it can, it prohibits economic development, in the
form of housing construction, power-plant
construction, and road construction. It attempts to
stop the opening of new mines and especially new oil
fields. While it claims to favor what it calls
renewable natural resources, it also attempts to
stop logging operations, even though new trees can
be grown to replace those removed. It has also
succeeded in imposing limits on the emission of such
chemicals as sulfur dioxide, nitrogen, and
chlorofluorocarbons (cfcs) into the atmosphere, and
in these cases systems of “tradable emissions
rights” have been established. It currently seeks
similarly to limit the emission of carbon dioxide
into the atmosphere and to establish a system of
tradable emission rights in its case too; indeed, a
limitation on carbon dioxide emissions and a system
of tradable emission rights for carbon dioxide
already exist in the European Union.
Under a system of tradable emission rights, the
government acknowledges long-standing emissions and
confers a legal right for them to continue. For
example, if for many years, a firm has been emitting
a ton of sulfur dioxide into the atmosphere each
year, the government may grant it a legal right to
continue doing so indefinitely and, in addition, to
sell that right in the market from year to year or
to sell it permanently, just as the firm might rent
or sell any other durable property that it owns.
Newcomers who wish to emit sulfur dioxide, or
established firms that wish to increase their
emissions, cannot do so unless they buy emission
rights from the firms that possess them. Emission
rights quickly become scarce and progressively more
valuable as the need for additional production of
the kind that must result in more emissions
intensifies and comes up against the barrier of the
prohibition on a larger volume of emissions.
I do not know of any reliable estimates of the
aggregate dollar value of the tradable emissions
that are now purchased in a given year in the United
States or around the world. But whatever it may be,
it represents a clear addition to the aggregate
amount of profits in the economic system. This is
because the firms that sell their emission rights
thereby have sales revenues for something that costs
them virtually nothing whatever to provide. And so
long as they sell these rights merely on an annual
basis or for a limited term of years these sales
revenues and profits will be recurring.
Furthermore, looking at things now from the
perspective of the purchasers of the emission
rights, the need to purchase emission rights
equivalently reduces the funds available to business
firms for the purchase of other things, notably
capital goods and labor services. Thus, the effect
of the existence of tradable emission rights is both
an increase in the aggregate amount of profit in the
economic system and a decrease in the aggregate
amount of wages paid in the economic system.
The effect of payments for emission rights on wages
can be further inferred from the following
considerations. Assume for the moment that the price
of emission rights were to count simply as an
additional cost of production, added to all of the
other costs of production, and to correspondingly
drive up the prices of goods to the point required
to cover this additional cost. If this happened, the
quantity of goods demanded in the economic system
would fall. It would fall simply as the result of
the combination of higher prices and limited funds
with which to pay prices.
The result of the fall in the quantity of goods
demanded would be unemployment. If unemployment is
to be avoided, the prices of goods must not rise.
But in order for them not to rise, their costs of
production must also not rise. In order for costs
not to rise in the face of the addition of the new
component of cost that is constituted by the price
of emission rights, another primary component of
cost, notably wages, must fall. In other words, the
value of tradable emission rights ends up being at
the expense of wages. Thus, environmentalism and the
system of tradable emission rights serve to raise
profits and reduce wages.
It must be stressed that if wage rates do not fall
in order to offset the additional costs constituted
by the value of tradable emission rights, then the
result is both higher prices and unemployment. In
this case, while wage rates in terms of money do not
fall, wage rates in terms of buying power still fall
because the same wage rates in money must be used to
pay higher prices for goods.
The fact that such are the consequences of the
system of tradable emission rights should not be
taken as a criticism simply of that system. The
imposition of the same environmentalist restrictions
on production without an accompanying system of
tradable emission rights would result in even worse
consequences. This is because the costs of complying
with the environmental regulations would then be far
greater, with the result either that prices would
have to rise or wage rates fall by that much more.
For example, a firm that could avoid a million
dollars of additional costs if it could emit an
additional ton of sulfur dioxide would simply have
to incur those additional costs even though
elsewhere in the economic system there was a firm
that would incur additional costs of only a few
thousand dollars if it reduced its emission of
sulfur dioxide by a ton. The absence of tradable
emission rights in this case would cause the
needless imposition of almost a million dollars of
unnecessary costs, requiring a corresponding rise in
prices or fall in wages in the economic system. It
is clearly the substantially lesser evil in this
case even if the right to emit a ton of sulfur
dioxide were to be sold for several hundred thousand
dollars.
The problem is not the system of tradable emission
rights. The problem is the prohibition of the
increase in emissions that is the necessary
accompaniment of the increase in production. The
prohibition of additional emissions thus serves to
prohibit the increase in production. Of course, in
the absence of prohibitions on additional emissions,
there would be no basis for the existence of systems
of tradable emission rights, and thus they would
simply not exist.
As indicated at the beginning of this article,
environmentalism’s prohibitions on production go far
beyond those that have been accompanied by systems
of tradable emission rights. With or without
tradable emission rights, the effect of imposing
laws and regulations based on environmentalism is to
make land and natural resources artificially scarce
relative to human labor and thus to enhance the
economic value of land and natural resources while
reducing the economic value of human labor, above
all, wage rates. In the terminology of the old
British classical economists, what environmentalism
is doing is increasing the portion of national
income that takes the form of “land rent,” and doing
it at the expense of the portion of national income
that is wages.
The rise in the economic value of land and natural
resources—the rise in land rent—shows up in the form
of a rise in profits. All net monetary earnings
derived from the ownership of land or natural
resources are profits from the point of view of
business accounting. Profits rise to the extent that
the prices of minerals and of agricultural products
rise relative to the costs of producing them. And
precisely this is what happens when the demand for
these products rises and environmentalism has
meanwhile succeeded in preventing commensurate
increases in their supply.
The leading example of this phenomenon at present is
the recent rise in the price of oil and natural gas.
A growing population and a growing need for oil here
in the US, coupled with major economic progress in
China and other parts of Asia, has substantially
increased the demand for oil and natural gas.
However, the environmental movement has done
everything in its power to prevent increases in the
supply of these commodities.
It has prevented the development not only of the oil
deposits in the North Slope of Alaska but also oil
and gas deposits on the continental shelf off
California and the Gulf Coast, as well as oil and
gas deposits present in the vast land areas set
aside as wilderness preserves and wildlife areas. In
addition, it has prevented the construction of new
atomic power plants, whose existence would serve to
diminish the demand for oil by the electric power
industry and thus make oil more available for other
purposes, and at a lower price. The same is true in
connection with coal mining. Its expansion too is
blocked, and thus the availability of this major
substitute for oil is also held back. The result is
that the need for oil is made that much more intense
and its price correspondingly higher.
Different parts of the supply of minerals and of
agricultural commodities have different costs of
production. For example, there are some petroleum
deposits which are so easily accessible and so
productive that they can be exploited at a cost of
production of perhaps just $3 or $4 per barrel. But
such petroleum deposits can meet only a small
portion of the demand. The rest of the demand must
be met by exploiting higher-cost deposits, deposits
with a cost of production of $10, $20, $30 per
barrel, and more. Every time the price of oil rises
because its supply is prevented from increasing,
profits are increased on all the petroleum deposits
in production.
The same principles apply to wheat production and
housing construction. The result of all increases in
demand not matched by an increase in supply, because
environmentalism prevents the increase in supply, is
a rise in price and an increase in the portion of
the good’s price that reflects the resulting greater
scarcity and higher value of land and natural
resources. And, as we have seen, this higher value
of the economic contribution of land and natural
resources that environmentalism causes takes the
form of higher profits.
In sharpest contrast to today’s markets that are
distorted by environmentalism and the government
intervention that it has brought about, a free
market would produce results of an opposite kind. In
a free market, with its powerful incentives to
increase production and to find new and more
efficient ways of doing so, supply would increase
not only commensurately with the increase in demand
but more than commensurately. Lower-cost methods of
production would be found that would make it
possible for prices to be driven down rather than
up. A free market operates to increase the supply of
useable, accessible land and mineral deposits
relative to the supply of human labor and thus to
make them progressively cheaper in real terms.
Accordingly, profits based on the ownership of
lower-cost natural resources and farm land would be
sharply contained, and even diminish, as scientific
and technological progress and capital accumulation
served to make available more such deposits and farm
land or equally good or better substitutes for them
and thus to drive the prices of products produced by
means of such deposits and land closer to their low
costs, meanwhile further reducing those low costs.
In a free market, wages rise relative to the value
of land and natural resources and are thus
correspondingly higher relative to profits. This was
the record of the United States and the rest of the
Western World for approximately 200 years following
the start of the Industrial Revolution.
Environmentalism is a movement dedicated to the
undoing of the Industrial Revolution. If not
checked, one of its results will be the progressive
reduction of wages and the further elevation of
profit incomes based on the ownership of land and
natural resources.
Monday, July 17, 2006
How Government Budget Deficits Reduce
Wages and Raise Profits
In recent years
there have been growing complaints over slow growth
in wages compared to profits. Those who make the
complaints usually offer little in the way of
explanation. Here is a part of the explanation:
growing government budget deficits.
Government budget deficits are financed partly by
the creation of new and additional money. But for
the rest, they are financed by selling government
securities to the citizens, who pay for the
securities with money that already exists and which
is part of their savings. If the government had not
been running at a deficit and had not needed to sell
these securities, the citizens would have used most
of the savings with which they buy the government
securities to buy corporate securities and in other
ways to make their funds available to business
firms.
Those savings, in the hands of business firms would
have been used to purchase capital goods and to pay
wages. These wages, however, never come into
existence if the savings out of which they would
have been paid are diverted to the government to
finance its deficit. Thus, wage payments in the
economic system are smaller because of government
deficits.
Yes, it is true that the government itself pays
wages to some extent. But it is unlikely to do so to
the same extent as do business firms. And to
whatever extent the additional wage payments it
makes out of the proceeds of its securities sales
are less than the wage payments that business firms
cannot make because of the diversion of part of what
would have been their capital funds to the
government, total wage payments in the economic
system are reduced.
In addition to this likely reduction in overall wage
payments in the economic system, the effect of
government budget deficits is an increase in the
aggregate, i.e., total, economy-wide, amount of
business profits. Here’s why.
Whether business gets money to finance its purchase
of capital goods and payment of wages, or the
government gets money to buy goods and services,
including meeting its own payroll, and, of course,
simply to give money away in carrying out various
welfare-state functions, the amount of business
sales revenues in the economic system will be pretty
much the same. This is because a dollar from the
sale of a good to a business firm and a dollar from
the sale of a good to the government is still a
dollar of sales revenues. A dollar from the sale of
a good to an employee of business or dollar from the
sale of a good to a government employee is again
still a dollar of sales revenues. And finally, a
dollar from the sale of a good to someone who has
received his money under one or another of the
government’s welfare-state programs is no less a
dollar of sales revenues than a dollar spent by
someone who had earned that dollar.
But here’s a crucial difference: The dollars spent
by business firms in buying capital goods and in
paying wages sooner or later show up as
costs of production. Those costs of
production, of course, must be deducted from sales
revenues in calculating profits. Aggregate profit in
the economic system reflects their subtraction.
To the extent that government budget deficits divert
funds from the purchase of capital goods and the
payment of wages by business firms, their effect is
sooner or later
to reduce the magnitude of costs of production in
the economic system and equivalently to increase the
aggregate amount of profit in the economic system.
Costs reflect prior outlays of money. To the extent
that those outlays are less, the costs will be less.
The reduction in costs of production raises profits
equivalently, because, as we have just seen, the
amount of sales revenues in the economic system is
the same either way; it’s the same with or without
the budget deficits. In the face of the same
aggregate sales revenues, reduced aggregate costs
mean equivalently higher profits.
So growing budget deficits are part of the
explanation of profits rising relative to wages.
Before concluding, it’s necessary to point out that
a rise in profits achieved in this way is not a
cause for joy. What is present is an illustration of
the dichotomy identified by Ricardo that often
exists between monetary value and physical wealth.
(See his
Principles of Political Economy and Taxation,
chap. XX.) Aggregate money profit is up, but in
large part that is the result simply of the
expenditure for capital goods being down. What that
signifies is less previously produced wealth being
available to serve in the production of future
wealth. A part of the output of the economic system
that would have gone into the production of future
output is instead diverted to the government’s
consumption and to the consumption of those to whom
the government gives money.
The effect of this cannot fail to be that the
productivity of labor in the economic system will be
less than it otherwise would have been and that real
wages in the future will consequently suffer from
production being less than it otherwise would have
been and thus from prices being higher than they
otherwise would have been. And, ironically, as an
integral part of these developments, while total
costs of production in the economic system, are
lower, unit costs of production will be higher than
they otherwise would have been, because of the
reduced output that results from the smaller total
outlays of business and the consequent reduction in
the supply of capital goods available for use in
further production.
In sum, the effect of government budget deficits is
lower money wages, higher money profits, and lower
real wages to the extent that the deficits serve to
increase prices and unit costs on top of reducing
money wages.
Tuesday, July 04, 2006
No Fourth of July Celebration at The New York
Times/Pravda
The New York Times
does not mention Independence Day on its editorial
page. And there is no word of celebration of it on
its Op-Ed page. What is present on the Op-Ed page is
a further demonstration of that newspaper’s
hostility to the fundamental values on which the
United States was built.
One article, titled
“Spinning the
Revolution,”
seeks to undercut the value of the American
Revolution by presenting it not as the kind of great
world-shaking event that it was, signifying for the
first time in human history the establishment of a
government dedicated to the protection of individual
rights, but as a matter of mere “spin,” manufactured
by a collection of writers and pamphleteers. In the
same vein, it belittles the value Americans have
rightly attached to the Declaration of Independence
and the United States Constitution by sarcastically
describing those documents as being viewed as
“sacred scripture."
Another article,
“Billionaires to
the Rescue,”
which compares Warren Buffet’s gift of $31 billion
to charity to the charitable giving of Andrew
Carnegie early in the last century, proceeds as
though it never heard of such a thing as the right
to the pursuit of happiness. Clearly revealing the
perspective of a collectivist, it dares to ask,
Is society served by permitting so much capital to
be accumulated by so few? Should we have to rely on
the usually unfulfilled hope that fortunes of this
magnitude will be put to a good cause? What becomes
of a society that must rely on "gifts" from a
handful of socially conscious billionaires to save
its schools, cure disease and alleviate poverty?
The
author believes that “society,” i.e., politicians
and government officials have the right to thwart
the individual’s accumulation of wealth, thereby
denying his right to the pursuit of happiness. In
claiming that it is an accidental matter whether
large fortunes are put to a good cause, he reveals
his ignorance of the fact that the fortunes are
invested in business firms as capital, and thereby
serve as the source of supply of goods and services
to consumers and of demand for the services of wage
earners. He demonstrates further ignorance in
failing to realize that the high profits out of
which fortunes are accumulated are the result of
introducing a series of important innovations in the
form of new and better products or more efficient
methods of production.
He also does not realize that all that prevents the
charitable giving of fortunes from resulting in a
reduction in the well-being of consumers and wage
earners is their continuing to remain invested
rather than being consumed by the recipients of
charity. The consumption of the recipients of
charity needs to be held within the limits of the
income on the capital in order for this destructive
outcome to be avoided.
Finally, seizing the fortunes by the government to
“save . . . schools, cure disease and alleviate
poverty” will accomplish little but the reduction of
capital. Schools, books, and all the means of
learning are properly the province of private
business firms meeting the demand of consumers, just
as is the supply of food and clothing. Likewise,
curing disease is properly the province of privately
owned pharmaceutical firms, hospitals, clinics, and
of physicians in private practice. The alleviation
of poverty is the daily work of businessmen who
introduce the newer and better products and more
efficient methods of production: in addition to
being the source of fortunes, these last are the
source of the rise in the standard of living of
everyone. They are what enable almost everyone in
the modern world to be well fed, clothed, and housed
and to have such goods as indoor plumbing, central
heating, refrigerators, stoves, telephones, and
television sets.
To the extent that schools, medical care, and
poverty represent problems in need of solution, the
first step in the solution is removing the
government from the picture and allowing the profit
motive and the pursuit of happiness to succeed in
solving these problems. That is a principle to be
remembered on America’s Independence Day.
These pathetic articles are what
The Times has to offer on the day
dedicated to the celebration of America’s existence.
It is an alien publication, dedicated to
collectivism and the worship of the State, to
principles the opposite of those on which the United
States was founded. Over the years, it has been the
champion of Stalin, of Mao, and of Castro, and more
recently, of the reincarnation of socialism known as
environmentalism. One cannot expect it to be the
champion of Washington and Jefferson and of the
United States. And it certainly is not.