Microsoft and Its
Enemies: Which Is the Monopolist?*
By
George Reisman**
Some months ago, at a hearing before the U.S.
Senate Judiciary Committee, the head of the Netscape corporation, a rival and antagonist
of Microsoft, asked the audience in the room how many owned a personal computer and then
how many of those used Microsoft's Windows operating system. Upon a show of hands
demonstrating that almost everyone in the room who owned a computer used Windows, the head
of Netscape concluded that he had just proved that Microsoft had a monopoly in
personal computer operating systems. No one in the room questioned his conclusion at the
time and, to my knowledge, no television commentator or newspaper reporter questioned it
later, when the incident was telecast and described in the press.
Everyone, it seems, took for granted the prevailing belief that the
essential feature of monopoly is that a given product or service is provided by just one
supplier. On this view of things, Microsoft, like Alcoa and Standard Oil before it,
belongs in the same category as the old British East India Company or such more recent
instances of companies with exclusive government franchises as the local gas or electric
company or the US Postal Service with respect to the delivery of first class mail. What
all of these cases have in common, and which is considered essential to the existence of
monopoly, according to the prevailing view, is that they all represent instances in which
there is only one seller. By the same token, what is not considered essential,
according to the prevailing view of monopoly, is whether the seller's position depends on
the initiation of physical force or, to the contrary, is achieved as the result of freedom
of competition and the choice of the market.
Dependence on the initiation of physical force was certainly present in
the case of the old British East India Company, which had exclusive control of British
trade with the East Indies only by virtue of a Royal grant of exclusive privilege and the
British government's readiness to back up that grant by means of the Royal Navy if any
competitor appeared on the scene to challenge it. The same dependence on a governmental
grant of exclusive privilege and on the government's readiness to stop potential
competitors by means of the initiation of physical force is present in all instances of
exclusive government franchises. It is present in the fact that should any competitor
enter the market and challenge the monopolist, the government dispatches an armed force to
stop him: the Royal Navy in the case of the British East India Company, and less glamorous
police-type forces, such as US Marshals or Postal Inspectors, in the more recent cases of
exclusive government franchises. Using physical force to stop economic competition
constitutes an initiation of physical force because the activity of economic
competition itself does not represent any use of physical force. If someone finds himself
dragged off to jail for selling spices from the Indies, electric power, natural gas, or
first-class mail delivery, he is clearly the victim of the initiation of physical force,
because the pursuit of such activities does not in any way constitute a prior use of
force.
Microsoft, Alcoa, and Standard Oil also represent cases of a sole
supplier, or at least come close to such a case. However, totally unlike the cases of
exclusive government franchises, their position in the market is not (or was not) the
result of the initiation of physical force but rather the result of their successful free
competition. That is, they became sole suppliers by virtue of being able to produce
products profitably at prices too low for other suppliers to remain in or enter the
market, or to produce products whose performance and quality others simply could not match
and could not compensate for by means of offering lower prices, inasmuch as they could not
be profitable at such lower prices. To say the same thing in different words, these three
companies achieved their position by means of offering their customers a combination of
better products and lower prices than any one else did or could.
This description of matters, incidentally, is confirmed, at least
implicitly, even by major antagonists of these firms. With respect to Standard Oil, the
U.S. Supreme Court declared in its 1911 decision breaking up the company: "Much has
been said in favor of the objects of the Standard Oil Trust, and what it has accomplished.
It may be true that it has improved the quality and cheapened the costs of petroleum and
its products to the consumer. But such is not one of the usual or general results of a
monopoly; and it is the policy of the law to regard, not what may, but what usually
happens."
(Ohio v. Standard Oil Co. 49 Ohio, 137 [1892]). Ironically, of course, in all the
years since, in utter contradiction of the facts cited by the Supreme Court, precisely
Standard Oil has been thought to be the standard by which the alleged evils of
"monopoly" are to be judged.
With respect to Alcoa, the presiding judge in the antitrust case against
it said: "It was not inevitable that it
should always anticipate increases in the demand for ingot and be prepared to supply them.
Nothing compelled it to keep doubling and redoubling its capacity before others entered
the field. It insists that it never excluded competitors; but we can think of no more
effective exclusion than progressively to embrace each new opportunity as it opened and to
face every newcomer with new capacity already geared into a great organization, having the
advantage of experience, trade connections and the elite of personnel." (Quoted in Ayn Rand,
Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal (New
York: New American Library, 1966), pp. 50-51.)
In this instance, the judge clearly appeared to
find no significant distinction between cases in which competitors were excluded by means
of physical force and cases in which they were "excluded" by means of superior
productive performance. Indeed, he seemed to think merely that the latter was a more
effective form of "exclusion."
Had the Supreme Court recognized the need to
distinguish between cases in which the status of sole supplier is the result of the
initiation of physical force and cases in which it is the result of free competition, it
would not have been surprised by what Standard Oil had accomplished. It would have
realized that what it described as the usual results of monopoly applied only to cases in
which the position of sole supplier was the result of the initiation of physical force.
Like Standard Oil and Alcoa, Microsoft's eminent status in its field is also the result of
productive accomplishment. Its productive accomplishments can be found in all of its
improvements in personal-computer operating systems from DOS 1.0 to Windows 98, and in its
growing leadership in providing applications that most successfully exploit these
improvements, such as word-processing, spreadsheet, database, and programming-language
programs. It has successfully overcome the competition of such seemingly well-entrenched
giants of the software industry as WordPerfect, Lotus 1-2-3, and Paradox and Borland
International (not to mention previously getting out from under the shadow of IBM). It has
accomplished this by providing software that the market judges to be substantially better
than these already excellent products.
What all this points to is that there is something very
wrong in thinking of monopoly as being constituted by any case in which there is just one
seller. The critical element is what is the foundation of that situation? Is it the
initiation of physical force by or on behalf of the seller or is it the seller's superior
performance under free competition? In the first case, there is something present that is
clearly against the interests of the buyers. The buyers are being forcibly deprived of
something that is better in order to allow the success of something that is worse and
could not succeed under free competition, i.e., without the aid of the initiation of
physical force. In the second case, the buyers are clearly better off: the sole seller is
the sole seller because his product or service is better than the alternatives, and the
buyers have chosen it and him over the alternatives. Here the result is the outcome of
free competition, not of its suppression.
Furthermore, once the status of sole seller is achieved
under the freedom of competition, it can be maintained only by that seller continuing to
offer a better combination of price and quality than any potential competitor. This is
because newcomers are free to challenge him at any time.
Once the essential importance of the presence or absence of
the initiation of physical force as the foundation of "monopoly" is recognized,
it becomes obvious that the concept of monopoly needs to be radically reformulated. It is
profoundly wrong to have a concept that groups together and thus treats as the same,
situations that are of a fundamentally opposite character. What's wrong with it is the
same sort of thing that would be wrong with putting both food and poison in the same
category and then either eating both or avoiding both.
What I suggest is a definition of monopoly that excludes
the results of free-market competition and includes only the results of forcible
violations of free-market competition. The definition, I suggest is, indeed, a modernized
version of the original, seventeenth-century definition of monopoly as an exclusive grant
of government privilege. To be specific, it is: Monopoly is a market or part of a market reserved to the exclusive possession
of one or more sellers by means of the initiation of physical force.
On this definition, of course, Standard Oil, Alcoa,
and Microsoft are not monopolies, while the old British East India Company, the U.S. Post
Office, and the local gas and electric companies, all operating under exclusive government
franchises, are monopolies. But what is equally significant about this definition and its
highlighting of exclusiveness based on the initiation of physical force is that it makes
possible the extension of the concept of monopoly to important instances constituting
violations of the freedom of competition other than those in which there is just one
seller of a given good or service.
For example, there are many thousands of French wheat
farmers. However, to the extent that France has a protective tariff designed to keep out
lower-priced foreign wheat and thereby to reserve the French wheat market to the exclusive
possession of French wheat farmers, French wheat farmers are given a monopoly of the
French wheat market. Similarly, to the extent that France or any country has, or has had,
legislation designed to protect large numbers of small merchants, such as butchers,
grocers, and haberdashers against the competition of more efficient large chains, that too
constitutes the forcible reservation of a market or segment of a market to the exclusive
possession of one set of producers and the simultaneous forcible exclusion from that
market of other producers. Such a situation is simultaneously monopoly for the
inefficient, protected producers and a violation of the freedoms of entry and competition
of the more efficient producers who are forcibly excluded from the market.
Indeed, seen in this light, while monopoly does not
necessarily exist when there is just one seller of a given good or service, it does exist
in a case in which the production of a good or service is legally open to everyone in a
society except for just one potential producer who otherwise would enter and
compete in that industry. That party's freedoms of entry and competition are violated. He
is forcibly excluded from the market, which is thereby monopolized against him. For
example, if early in the present century, the US government had declared that the
production of automobiles was legally open to everyone with the single exception of Henry
Ford, or the single exception of General Motors, its action would simultaneously have
constituted a violation of the freedoms of entry and competition of these parties and the
monopolization of the automobile industry against them--with, of course, very serious
negative consequences for the future development of the automobile industry and the
standard of living of the average person.
Precisely this is the present situation of Bill Gates
and Microsoft. So far from being a monopolist, they are the targets of promonopoly
interference by the US government. Precisely, this is what exists when the government
seeks to reserve the internet browser market, or any part of that market, to Netscape and
others--when it says, in effect, all shall be allowed to enter and compete in this market except
Gates and Microsoft, who are to be forcibly excluded from that market either totally or in
part.
Gates and Microsoft have already been the victims of
promonopoly interference by the US government when they were prohibited from culminating
their purchase of the Intuit Corporation and its leading software product Quicken. They
had wanted to enter an important segment of the market for computer financial software and
associated computer financial services through that purchase. But they could not. They
were forcibly excluded from that market. Their freedoms of entry and competition were
violated. The market was monopolized against them.
I believe that as a result of that act of
monopolization against Gates and Microsoft, I and many other computer users have been
deprived of such potential advances as the ability easily to integrate the generation of
invoices with inventory control, which would have been a likely outcome of Microsoft's
integrating the features of Quicken with its existing database programs, such as Access.
That couldn't happen, because the government decided to protect me from Microsoft.
Now the government wants to protect me from
Microsoft's web browser. I can only say that as a buyer of computer software, I don't want
this sort of "protection." I want the right to choose to buy or not buy anything
Microsoft wants to sell me and the right to accept anything they want to give me when I
buy their Windows operating system. I see no more good reason to reserve the internet
browser market, or any part of that market to Netscape, than I see to reserve the market
for pork chops to a special set of pork butchers. It's the same kind of promonopoly
interference.
I am confident that no matter what eminence Microsoft
may go on to achieve, it will not be able to maintain that eminence once any newcomer
appears who can do the job still better. This is certainly what is taught by the recent
experience of IBM, the seemingly most impregnable giant of the computer industry. It is
what is taught by the recent experience of such other, even bigger economic giants as
General Motors and AT&T. The essential point is that under the legal freedoms of entry
and competition, a firm remains the biggest and the best, and perhaps the one and only,
only so long as no one appears who makes the
best still better.
For further reading on this
subject, see:
George Reisman,
Capitalism: A Treatise
on Economics (Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books,
1996), Chapter 10.
Ayn
Rand, Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal
(New York: New American
Library, 1966), Chapter 3 and the appendix
"Man's Rights."
|